The “Whence” of Evil and How the Demiurge Can Alleviate Our Suffering
Abstract
:1. Introduction
2. The Creation and Its Probable Purpose
3. Ancient Theodicies for Modern Times
4. The Demiurge’s World and Its Ontology
5. Conclusions
Funding
Conflicts of Interest
References
- Adams, Marilyn M. 1999. Horrendous Evils and the Goodness of God. Ithaca: Cornell University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Adams, Marilyn M., and Robert M. Adams, eds. 1990. The Problem of Evil. Oxford: Oxford University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Aiken, H. D. 1957/58. God and Evil: Some Relations between Faith and Morals. Ethics 68: 77–97. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Badawi, Abdurrahman. 1963. Muhhamad ibn Zakariya al-Razi. In A History of Muslim Philosophy, Volume I. Edited by M. M. Sharif. Weisbaden: Otto Harrassowitz, pp. 434–49. [Google Scholar]
- Bilimoria, Purushottama. 2013. Toward and Indian Theodicy. In The Blackwell Companion to the Problem of Evil. Edited by Justin P. McBrayer and Daniel Howard-Snyder. Chichester: Wiley-Blackwell, pp. 281–95. [Google Scholar]
- Braiterman, Zachary. 1998. (God) After Auschwitz: Tradition and Change in Post-Holocaust Jewish Thought. Princeton: Princeton University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Bremmer, Jan N. 2002. The Rise and Fall of the Afterlife. London and New York: Routledge. [Google Scholar]
- Brightman, Edgar Sh. 1940. A Philosophy of Religion. New York: Prentice-Hall, Inc. [Google Scholar]
- Buckareff, Andrei A., and Yujin Nagasawa, eds. 2016. Alternative Concepts of God: Essays on Metaphysics of the Divine. Oxford: Oxford University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Chatterjee, Satishchandra, and Dhirendramohan Datta. 1984. An Introduction to Indian Philosophy, 8th ed. Calcutta: University of Calcutta. [Google Scholar]
- Cornford, Francis M. 1997. Plato’s Cosmology: The Timaeus of Plato. Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing Company. First published 1937. [Google Scholar]
- Dasgupta, Surendranath. 1975. A History of Indian Philosophy: Volume I. Delhi: Motilal Banarsidass Publishers. [Google Scholar]
- Draper, Paul. 1989. Pain and Pleasure: An Evidential Problem for Theists. Nous 23: 331–50. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
- Fletcher, William. 1871. The Works of Lactantius. Edinburgh: T.&T. Clark, vol. II. [Google Scholar]
- Ford, Lewis. 1992. Divine Persuasion and the Triumph of God. In The Problem of Evil: Selected Readings. Edited by Michael L. Peterson. Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press, pp. 247–65. [Google Scholar]
- Gambhirananda, Swami. 1965. Brahma Sūtra Bhāṣya of Śaṅkarācārya. Kolkata: Advaita Ashrama. [Google Scholar]
- Greene, William C. 1948. Moira: Fate, Good and Evil in Greek Thought. Cambridge: Harvard University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Gregory, Andrew. 2007. Ancient Greek Cosmogony. London: Bristol Classical Press. [Google Scholar]
- Hartshorne, Charles, and William L. Reese, eds. 2000. Philosophers Speak of God. Amherst: Humanity Books. First published 1953. [Google Scholar]
- Herman, Arthur L. 1971. Indian Theodicy: Śaṁkara and Rāmānuja on Brahma Sūtra II. 1. 32–36. Philosophy East and West 21: 265–81. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Herman, Arthur L. 1976. The Problem of Evil and Indian Though, 2nd ed. Delhi: Motilal Banarsidass Publishers. [Google Scholar]
- Hick, John. 2010. Evil and the God of Love. 3rd reissue. Hampshire: Palgrave Macmillan. [Google Scholar]
- Hiriyanna, M. 1995. The Essentials of Indian Philosophy. Delhi: Motilal Banarsidass Publishers. [Google Scholar]
- Howard-Snyder, Daniel, ed. 1996. The Evidential Argument from Evil. Bloomington: Indiana University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Hume, David. 2007. Dialogues Concerning Natural Religion and Other Writings. Edited by Coleman D. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. First published 1779. [Google Scholar]
- Ilievski, Viktor. 2016. Plato’s Theodicy in the Timaeus. Rhizomata 4: 201–24. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Kahn, Charles H. 2001. Pythagoras and the Pythagoreans: A Brief History. Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing Company. [Google Scholar]
- Keith, A. Berriedale. 1909. Pythagoras and the Doctrine of Transmigration. Journal of the Royal Asiatic Society of Great Britain and Ireland 41: 569–606. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
- Keller, James A. 2013. Process Theism and Theodicies for Problems of Evil. In The Blackwell Companion to the Problem of Evil. Edited by Justin P. McBrayer and Daniel Howard-Snyder. Chichester: Wiley-Blackwell, pp. 340–48. [Google Scholar]
- Kushner, Harold S. 1981. When Bad Things Happen to Good People. New York: Random House Inc. [Google Scholar]
- Leftow, Brian. 2009. Omnipotence. In The Oxford Handbook of Philosophical Theology. Edited by Thomas P. Flint and Michael C. Rea. Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 167–98. [Google Scholar]
- Leibniz, Gottfried W. 2007. Theodicy: Essays on the Goodness of God, the Freedom of Man and the Origin of Evil. Edited by A. Farrer. Translated by E. M. Huggard. Charleston: BiblioBazaar. First published 1710. [Google Scholar]
- Lipner, Julius J. 1986. The Face of Truth: A Study of Meaning and Metaphysics in the Vedantic Theology of Ramanuja. London: Macmillan Press. [Google Scholar]
- Lovejoy, Arthur O. 1936. The Great Chain of Being: A Study of the History of an Idea. Cambridge: Harvard University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Mackie, John L. 1955. Evil and Omnipotence. Mind 64: 200–212. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Mackie, John. L. 1982. The Miracle of Theism: Arguments For and Against the Existence of God. Oxford: Oxford University Press. [Google Scholar]
- McCloskey, H. J. 1960. God and Evil. Philosophical Quarterly 10: 97–114. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Mobini, Mohammad A. 2013. Earth’s Epistemic Fruits for the Harmony with God: An Islamic Theodicy. In The Blackwell Companion to the Problem of Evil. Edited by Justin P. McBrayer and Daniel Howard-Snyder. Chichester: Wiley-Blackwell, pp. 296–308. [Google Scholar]
- Nietzsche, Freidrich W. 1962. Philosophy in the Tragic Age of the Greeks. Translated by Marianne Cowan. Washington, DC: Regnery Publishing, Inc. First published 1873. [Google Scholar]
- O’Flaherty, Wendy D. 1976. The Origins of Evil in Hindu Mythology. Berkley and Los Angeles: University of California Press. [Google Scholar]
- Oppy, Graham. 2017. Logical Arguments from Evil and Free-Will Defences. In The Cambridge Companion to the Problem of Evil. Edited by Chad Meister and Paul K. Moser. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 45–64. [Google Scholar]
- Perrine, Timothy, and Stephen J. Wykstra. 2017. Skeptical Theism. In The Cambridge Companion to the Problem of Evil. Edited by Chad Meister and Paul K. Moser. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 85–107. [Google Scholar]
- Peters, Francis E. 2003. The Monotheists: Jews, Christians and Muslims in Conflict and Competition, Volume II: The Words and Will of God. Princeton: Princeton University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Peterson, Michael L. 2008. Eschatology and Theodicy. In The Oxford Handbook of Eschatology. Edited by Jerry L. Walls. Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 518–33. [Google Scholar]
- Pinnock, Clark, Richard Rice, John Sanders, William Hasker, and David Basinger. 1994. The Openness of God: A Biblical Challenge to the Traditional Understanding of God. Downers Grove: InterVarsity Press. [Google Scholar]
- Roth, John K. 2004. Theistic Antitheodicy. American Journal of Theology & Philosophy 25: 276–93. [Google Scholar]
- Rouzati, Nasrin. 2018. Evil and Human Suffering in Islamic Thought—Towards a Mystical Theodicy. Religions 9: 47. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
- Rowe, William L. 1979. The Problem of Evil and Some Varieties of Atheism. American Philosophical Quarterly 16: 335–41. [Google Scholar]
- Rowe, William L. 1984. Evil and the Theistic Hypothesis: A Response to Wykstra. International Journal for Philosophy of Religion 16: 95–100. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Rowe, William L. 1986. The Empirical Argument from Evil. In Rationality, Religious Belief, and Moral Commitment: New Essays in the Philosophy of Religion. Edited by Robert Audi and William J. Wainwright. Ithaca: Cornell University Press, pp. 227–47. [Google Scholar]
- Rowe, William L. 1996. The Evidential Argument from Evil: A Second Look. In The Evidential Argument from Evil. Edited by Daniel Howard-Snyder. Bloomington: Indiana University Press, pp. 262–85. [Google Scholar]
- Ruse, Michael. 2017. Naturalism, Evil, and God. In The Cambridge Companion to the Problem of Evil. Edited by Chad Meister and Paul K. Moser. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 124–43. [Google Scholar]
- Sharma, B. N. K. 1997. Madhva’s Teachings in His Own Words. Mumbai: Bharatiya Vidya Bhavan. [Google Scholar]
- Sobel, Jordan H. 2004. Logic and Theism: Arguments For and Against Beliefs in God. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Sorabji, Richard. 1983. Time, Creation and the Continuum: Theories in Antiquity and the Early Middle Ages. London: Duckworth. [Google Scholar]
- Strawson, Galen. 2012. What Can Be Proven About God? Letter to the Editor, The New York Review of Books, December 6. [Google Scholar]
- Stump, Eleonore. 2010. Wandering in Darkness: Narrative and the Problem of Suffering. Oxford: Oxford University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Swinburne, Richard. 1973. Omnipotence. American Philosophical Quarterly 10: 231–37. [Google Scholar]
- Swinburne, Richard. 1988. Does Theism need a Theodicy? Canadian Journal of Philosophy 18: 287–311. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Tooley, Michael. 2012. Inductive Logic and the Probability that God Exists: Farewell to Skeptical Theism. In Probability in the Philosophy of Religion. Edited by Jake Chandler and Victoria S. Harrison. Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 144–64. [Google Scholar]
- Trakakis, Nick N. 2007. The God Beyond Belief: In Defense of William Rowe’s Evidential Argument from Evil. Dordrecht: Springer. [Google Scholar]
- Trakakis, Nick N. 2013. Antitheodicy. In The Blackwell Companion to the Problem of Evil. Edited by Justin P. McBrayer and Daniel Howard-Snyder. Chichester: Wiley-Blackwell, pp. 363–75. [Google Scholar]
- Trakakis, Nick N. 2017. Anti-Theodicy. In The Cambridge Companion to the Problem of Evil. Edited by Chad Meister and Paul K. Moser. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 124–43. [Google Scholar]
- Uskokov, Aleksandar. forthcoming. Philosophy of the Brahma-sutra. London: Bloomsbury.
- Van Inwagen, Peter. 2006. The Problem of Evil. Oxford: Oxford University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Van Woudenberg, René. 2013. A Brief History of Theodicy. In The Blackwell Companion to the Problem of Evil. Edited by Justin P. McBrayer and Daniel Howard-Snyder. Chichester: Wiley-Blackwell, pp. 177–91. [Google Scholar]
- Vasu, Rai Bahadur Ch. 1979. The Vedanta Sutras of Badarayana with the commentary of Baladeva, 2nd ed. New Delhi: Munshiram Manoharlal. [Google Scholar]
- Vireswarananda, Swami, and Swami Addevananda. 1995. Brahma-Sutras: Shri Bhashya. Calcuta: Advaita Ashrama. [Google Scholar]
- Vlastos, Gregory. 1939. The Disorderly Motion in the Timaios. The Classical Quarterly 33: 71–83. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Whitehead, Alfred N. 1978. Process and Reality: An Essay in Cosmology, Corrected Edition. Edited by David Ray Griffin and Donald W. Sherburne. New York: Free Press. First published 1929. [Google Scholar]
- Winter, Timothy. 2017. Islam and the Problem of Evil. In The Cambridge Companion to the Problem of Evil. Edited by Chad Meister and Paul K. Moser. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 230–48. [Google Scholar]
- Wykstra, Stephen J. 1984. The Humean Obstacle to Evidential Arguments from Suffering: On Avoiding the Evils of ‘Appearance’. International Journal for Philosophy of Religion 16: 73–93. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Wykstra, Stephen J. 1996. Rowe’s Noseeum Argument from Evil. In The Evidential Argument from Evil. Edited by Daniel Howard-Snyder. Bloomington: Indiana University Press, pp. 126–50. [Google Scholar]
1 | That is, the omnibenevolent, omniscient and omnipotent deity who creates the world ex nihilo. By the end of this paper it should become clear that the concept I presently adhere to is somewhat different. In a word, with the term “God”, I denote the supreme omnibenevolent and omniscient being, the fountainhead of consciousness and bliss, who generates the world by ordering the primordial stuff of creation and infuses it with life and goodness, as far as possible. |
2 | This tripartite division of evil and its nomenclature was probably introduced by Leibniz, despite his claims of rootedness in tradition. In the Theodicy, where it first appears, Leibniz is not very verbal about the concepts, and all he gives is the following: “Evil may be taken metaphysically, physically and morally. Metaphysical evil consists in mere imperfection, physical evil in suffering, and moral evil in sin” (Leibniz [1710] 2007, p. 39). Through the centuries, the metaphysical aspect of the problem has somehow slipped out of the picture, but that might not have been the best maneuver. |
3 | See (Fletcher 1871, p. 28). Hume’s famous rendering in the Dialogues Concerning Natural Religion (Hume [1779] 2007, p. 74), is but a simplified version of the same argument. |
4 | This remains so besides some recent efforts to revive the argument, the latest one being (Oppy 2017). |
5 | It is worth mentioning that Stump’s is an especially thorough and commendable attempt to produce a cogent defense, carried out in a dialectical way and attentive to even minor details. |
6 | For an overview and apology of the skeptical theism responses, see (Perrine and Wykstra 2017). |
7 | This is the old, poignant Dostoyevsky-style objection, which has an especially strong effect on our affective cognition. Similar considerations have compelled some theists to shrink from the attempts to exculpate God in the face of evils, and qualify them as fruitless, or even morally dubious. These are the so-called anti-theodicists. See, e.g., (Roth 2004) and (Trakakis 2013, 2017), while for the opposite view, i.e., the one promoting the positive potential of, and the need for, theodicy, see (Hick 2010, pp. 6–11; Swinburne 1988). |
8 | |
9 | To reiterate, this seems to be the assumption rooted in the minds of many contemporary advocates of the argument for evil. It is interesting to note that Hume in his Dialogues (Hume [1779] 2007, p. 72) presents a simple deduction meant to prove this assumption false. Thus, from the presupposed infinity of divine power and the fact that no man or animal is truly happy, Hume concludes that God does not will their happiness; from the infinity of divine wisdom and industry, and the fact that “nature tends not to human or animal felicity”, he concludes that nature does not have that purpose. Hume’s alleged reason for applying this argument is to demonstrate that God’s morality is incomparable and incompatible with that of humans, while he in fact covertly intends to induce skeptical, or even anti-theistic, understanding in the minds of his readers. |
10 | It is worth pointing out that the notion of purposeful, purificatory suffering was a key component of the Islamic theodicies as well, most notably of those of Rūmī and al-Ghazālī (see Rouzati 2018, pp. 4–13). The essential information on the problem of evil as confronted by the Islamic thinkers can be gathered from the concise and useful discussions in (Mobini 2013; Winter 2017). |
11 | As it is clearly impossible, within the scope of a single paper, to make a case for most of the complex issues that will be touched upon here, including the existence of free will, plausibility of transmigration theory, compatibility of monotheism with dualist/pluralist ontology—to mention just a few. |
12 | It would not be an exaggeration to say that the mental state of resignation, or even despair, (bearing within itself the seed of philosophical/spiritual inquiry) forms a significant part of our daily life and culture. Thus, people often find that in comparison to the inevitability of disease and death, much of what they crave or aim for is overrated. These feelings have been amply expressed in literature (e.g., Dostoyevsky’s Crime and Punishment, Sartre’s Age of Reason, Nausea, Beckett’s Proust, Waiting for Godot), but also in popular culture—it will suffice to point out Pink Floyd’s masterpiece album “The Wall”, and the recent grim description of the American day-to-day life in a black comedy movie with a telling title: “I don’t feel at home in this world anymore”. |
13 | As they both share resemblances with all theodicies that focus on the eschaton. For an overview of those and further references, see (Peterson 2008). |
14 | This does not imply the necessity of self-denial on the part of the individual of the kind criticized by Stump in (2010, pp. 420–32); it rather requires acceptance of the unavoidable and awareness that happiness in separation from the divine is, ultimately, impossible. |
15 | That is to say that for the purposes of this paper, I take the self to be an individuated transmigrating soul, fundamentally disassociated from the various identities it assumes during its myriads of embodiments. |
16 | Interestingly enough, not everybody would agree that Plato is even interested in PoE, or that he proposes a theodicy at all; however, since I tried to demonstrate the opposite elsewhere (Ilievski 2016), that question will not be an object of my interest here. |
17 | See Cleanthes’ Hymn to Zeus, lines 17 and 21–25. |
18 | The idea is plain: a person born in a fishing village in the Philippines and a descendant of a British university professor clearly do not have equal chances of earning a teaching position at the University College London during their lifetime. However, the assumption advanced by Plato is that there was a phase when they were complete equals; the fact that their respective futures have developed differently from that point on is ultimately upon them alone and has nothing to do with God. Plato’s demiurge is quite explicit on this. |
19 | Most notably Pythagoras (see, e.g., Xenophanes’ B7 DK, Porphyry’s VP 19), and Empedocles (B117 DK, B127 DK). Kahn (2001, pp. 18–19) claims, not without some supportive argumentation, that Pythagoras most probably borrowed this doctrine from the Indians. For an older and more adamant statement to the same effect, see (Keith 1909, pp. 569–70). For orphism and reincarnation, see (Bremmer 2002, pp. 23–24). For the beginnings of the rebirth theory in India, see (Dasgupta 1975, pp. 53–57). |
20 | This statement is applicable to the Indian concept of karma, where the gods are also subjected to karmic laws. In cannot be transposed to Plato, whose gods have fixed sempiternal positions (see Tim. 41a–b). |
21 | As postulated already in the Upaniṣads (e.g., Bṛhadāraṇyaka Up. IV.4.5–6, Kaṭha Up. II.2.7, Praśna Up. III.7), in the Bhagavad-gītā (e.g., 2.51, 3.9), but also, by and large, in Plato: (e.g., Gorg. 523a–b, Phd. 113d–114c, Rep. 615a–c, Leg. 904a–e). For a concise exposition of the karma doctrine, see (Chatterjee and Datta 1984, pp. 15–17; Dasgupta 1975, pp. 71–74; Hiriyanna 1995, pp. 46–50). The cause of present suffering is usually located in previous lives, because it takes some time for the karma seeds to fructify. |
22 | Thus, also Plotinus: “But in the past he inflicted [upon others] those things he presently suffers” (alla ēn pote tauta poiēsas, ha nyn esti paschōn, Enn. III.2.13.13). |
23 | An overview of the Vedānta theodicy, focused primarily on Śaṅkara and Rāmānuja, is given in (Bilimoria 2013, pp. 288–93). |
24 | See (Herman 1971, pp. 265–70). For an associated conception of the world as a play of a god, see Heraclitus B 52 DK, with Nietzsche’s interpretation in (Nietzsche [1873] 1962, pp. 57–68). |
25 | For a thorough elaboration of these three approaches to the līlā theory, see (Uskokov forthcoming, ch. III). |
26 | For the same conclusion in Śaṅkara’s and Baladeva’s commentaries, see (Gambhirananda 1965, pp. 360–65), (Vasu 1979, p. 268). See also (Herman 1971, pp. 271–73). |
27 | See, e.g., Baladeva’s position in (Vasu 1979, pp. 268–70; O’Flaherty 1976, pp. 17–19). |
28 | Herman (1976, pp. 263–64) recognizes the regress, but considers it non-vicious. |
29 | See (Hiriyanna 1995, p. 49). In particular the difficult circumstances, which may be understood as giving us a strong impetus for moral and spiritual betterment. In fact, the appeal to this kind of approach to the challenging circumstances was one of the main theodicean strategies of the stoics (see, e.g., Seneca’s De Providentia I.6, II.1–4). |
30 | The first recorded appearances of the ex operibus dei reasoning are probably in Xenophon’s Memorabilia I.4.2–7, and Plato’s Philebus 29d–e and Laws 886a2–4. |
31 | For Plotinus, non-discursive, intuitive knowledge represented the crown of philosophical training and practice (see Enn. I.3); it also empowered the Indian saints, both the heterodox—like Buddha and Mahāvīra—and the Vedic seers, to influence so profoundly their followers and humanity in general. |
32 | Different versions of this theory were held by Aristotle, Theophrastus, Plutarch, Plotinus, later on by Leibniz, and in the 20th century by (Vlastos 1939), to a degree by (Cornford [1937] 1997, pp. 206–8; Greene 1948, p. 331), and others. |
33 | Indeed, Plato’s demiurge wills to make everything excellent, and leave nothing bad, as far as that is possible (kata dynamin, Tim. 30a, etc.). This oft-repeated phrase makes it clear that there are fits the demiurge cannot accomplish. That may, or may not make him non-omnipotent, as it will be argued in the next section. |
34 | Most notably in (Whitehead [1929] 1978, Process and Reality), and (Hartshorne and Reese [1953] 2000, Philosophers Speak of God). |
35 | This may also be seen as one version of what Brightman calls “finite theism”. His historical overview of this tendency in theism, starting with Plato and ending with Whitehead and other 20th century thinkers, is given in (Brightman 1940, pp. 286–301). An important recent work on alternative concepts of God is (Buckareff and Nagasawa 2016), with Chapters 5, 6, and 7 being particularly relevant to the topic of this paper. |
36 | It may not be superfluous to emphasize that I do not subscribe to any kind of Ditheism of the Manichean type. Matter is neither God’s rival, nor—being non-sentient—a rebellious entity in the real sense of the word; it remains infinitely inferior and eternally subordinated to him. Therefore, my suggestion should better be tagged as “soft dualism”, instead of “dualism” simpliciter. |
37 | That soft ontological dualism or pluralism is not incompatible with strict monotheism was shown by those monotheistic thinkers who accommodated within their ontologies entities uncreated and coeternal with God, though subordinated to him, like, e.g., al-Rāzī (five principles: God, soul, matter, time, space; see (Badawi 1963, pp. 440–45)); Baladeva (five principles: God, soul, matter, time, karma; see (Vasu 1979, pp. 2–3, 269)); Mādhvācārya (three principles: God, soul, matter; see (Sharma 1997)). |
38 | This need not mean that the world’s creation occurs in time, because it can be argued that the latter emerges jointly with the world. God’s mode of existence and activity is non-durational eternity, which our inescapably temporal parlance fails to grasp and describe. The question of the transition from ungenerated to generated state and the associated problem of the period of divine inactivity that precedes the latter thus become redundant. |
39 | “[T]he problem of evil … arises only for a religion which insists that the object of its worship is at once perfectly good and unlimitedly powerful” (Hick 2010, p. 4). See also (Mackie 1955, p. 200; van Woudenberg 2013, p. 177). |
40 | Such is, e.g., the process theodicy. For accounts and defenses of process theodicy, see (Ford 1992; Keller 2013). |
41 | For a brief clarification of this position, see (Keller 2013, p. 344). |
42 | See Bhagavad-gītā 18.70. In addition, Trakakis’ assumption (2007, p. 341) that—in order to serve as a useful tool in counteracting the problem of evil—the limitation of God’s power should go all the way to excluding everything that is empirically impossible, need not be always acceptable. I see no problem in postulating a divinity, analogous to the demiurge, who is capable of performing supernatural acts (creating the world would certainly be one of those), but still “powerless” both to prevent the Titanic from sinking (on account of the passengers’ karma), and to alter the natural law that terrestrial animals cannot survive long underwater. |
43 | For the intriguing claim that a satisfactory account of omnipotence is reached upon positing an omnipotent being who is not necessitated to preserve his omnipotence omnitemporally, see (Swinburne 1973); for additional difficulties with omnipotence, see (Sobel 2004, pp. 345–68); for a brief overview of the classical accounts—from Origen to Ockham—thorough analysis of some influential recent definitions, and a sophisticated novel input, see (Leftow 2009). |
44 | See (Leftow 2009, p. 169). |
45 | This understanding follows in the wake of an ancient thesis, conveniently summed up in the ex nihil nihilo fit maxim. For philosophical arguments in favor of eternity of matter and against the creatio ex nihilo concept advanced by al-Rāzī, see (Badawi 1963, p. 444). |
46 | One may also follow a different course and try both to preserve omnipotence and avoid dualism, by arguing that God’s being could include materiality as a fundamental, but not chosen part of the All. Omnipotence would then mean that to be able to do anything metaphysically possible, the restrictions imposed by the non-chosen aspect of materiality would be beyond the scope of the latter (I owe this insight to an anonymous referee). It seems to me that a similar tendency is discernible in the theology of Rāmānuja, who sees God and the world (together with the individual souls) as standing in a soul-body relationship. God and matter form an organic unity, with the latter being inseparable from the former, but still not identical to him (see Lipner 1986, p. 37). Rāmānuja thus tries to accommodate a coeternal material principle within the framework of his eminently monistic approach. |
47 | That is, such a god would be triply “impeded”, but still all-powerful. First, he would be internally conditioned by his own omnibenevolent nature to produce the creation. Second, and most importantly, his range of choices of generatable possible worlds would be limited by the characteristics of the raw material of creation. Finally, he would be prompted by the decree of his will to respect the law of karma, instituted—just as any natural law—by him alone. Nevertheless, these impediments would not be detrimental to God’s omnipotence, because they are either self-imposed, or lie outside the (newly established) boundaries of the metaphysically possible. |
48 | Someone may object that offering three answers to a single question is an overkill: a single strategy, e.g., the non-pliability of matter, should suffice as a solution to PoE. However, this is not so. To take a different example, the personal responsibility solution taken by itself might not be adequate to account for the phenomenon of natural evil, etc. Thus, I believe that all three suggested strategies are indispensable as constituents of a single solution: the first one answers the question “why a world at all?”; the second and the third, strictly speaking, dispose of the moral and natural aspect of PoE respectively, although the borderlines in this case are blurred to a significant degree. |
49 | A very striking example of such emotion is given in the Bhāgavata Purāṇa I.8.25, where Queen Kunti, who has been subjected—together with her family—to great injustice and prolonged suffering, offers the following prayer to Kṛsṇa: vipadaḥ santu tāḥ śaśvat tatra tatra jagad-guro/bhavato darśanaṁ yat syād apunar bhava-darśanam“—O universal guru, let these calamities befall us over and over again, so that we could keep on seeing you, for thus our repeated births and deaths will cease.” |
50 | A very recent definition of theodicy, for example, is cashed out in the following words: “A theodicy … is a reasonable or plausible justification of God’s permission of evil, where this consists in delineating what might be … God’s purposes for allowing evil” (Trakakis 2017, p. 124, emphasis added). |
© 2020 by the author. Licensee MDPI, Basel, Switzerland. This article is an open access article distributed under the terms and conditions of the Creative Commons Attribution (CC BY) license (http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/).
Share and Cite
Ilievski, V. The “Whence” of Evil and How the Demiurge Can Alleviate Our Suffering. Religions 2020, 11, 137. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel11030137
Ilievski V. The “Whence” of Evil and How the Demiurge Can Alleviate Our Suffering. Religions. 2020; 11(3):137. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel11030137
Chicago/Turabian StyleIlievski, Viktor. 2020. "The “Whence” of Evil and How the Demiurge Can Alleviate Our Suffering" Religions 11, no. 3: 137. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel11030137
APA StyleIlievski, V. (2020). The “Whence” of Evil and How the Demiurge Can Alleviate Our Suffering. Religions, 11(3), 137. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel11030137