Hasidic Myth-Activism: Martin Buber’s Theopolitical Revision of Volkish Nationalism
Abstract
:1. Introduction
2. Buber and Volkish Thought
2.1. Volkish Thought in Past and Contemporary Times
2.2. Volkish Thought
2.3. George Mosse on Buber’s Zionism and the Volkish Spirit
The terminology of sickness (Almog 1991; Krochmalnik 1997), the dialectic of decay and renewal (Biemann 2009), and the merging of nationalist and humanist sensibilities, which already characterized Moses Hess’s “proto-Zionism,” likewise provided the intellectual premises for Buber’s rediscovery of Hasidism. Mosse points to the striking similarity between Buber’s Hasidism and the renewed interest in the German mystics, like Meister Eckhart and Jacob Böhme.12 Each reflected a new appreciation of mythos as an alternative to structured religion and of community as an alternative to mechanical—and urban—society (Mosse [1970] 1987, p. 87). This new unio mystica was imagined as the reunification of the individual soul with the “organic” community of the Volk. This image adhered to the common distinction made in turn-of-the-century German thought between artificial community (Gesellschaft) and genuine community (Gemeinschaft), which was adopted equally by left and right ideologies, nationalists and anarchists, as a vehicle for national identity and mystic redemption (Mosse [1970] 1987, pp. 91–92).played the same role in the Jewish context of the fin de siècle that Paul de Lagarde played in the German context [in renewing the Culture], but with a significant difference: whereas Lagarde exalted the specifically Germanic, Buber sought to transcend the specific Volk in order to bring into being an all-embracing humanism.
2.4. Some Trends Interpreting Buber as a Volkish Thinker
2.5. Nationalism and Universalism: Attempts to Reconcile the Conflicting Trends in Buber’s Writings
Tal suggests that these two tendencies be construed as complementary and in dialogue with one another, rather than as contradictory (pp. 39, 42). A comparable attempt to reconcile these dimensions of Buber’s thought has since been made by Steven Aschheim in his book Beyond the Border (2007). Aschheim explores Buber in the broader context of Brith Shalom, arguing that “indeed, it is one of the more interesting paradoxes of this group [Bi-nationalists, Brith Shalom] that the most non-chauvinist Zionist nationalism was closely associated with various forms of organic, existential, and totalistic Volkish visions and ideology” (Aschheim 2007, p. 24).20 Aschheim explains this affinity in terms of a fusion: “[T]he binationalists were able to fuse the two [tendencies] by dismissing the hierarchical and power-political Herrschaft dimensions of Volkish ideology and deploying it in the direction of “culture” and spirit, the moral and inner-directed realm (properties that characterized the German-Jewish intellectual legacy as a whole)” (Aschheim 2007, p. 24). However, Aschheim’s distinction between a cultural Buber (who pronounces Volkish ideas) and a political Buber (who stresses the value of universalism and humanism) is not fully satisfying. Uri Ram, for instance, has challenged this notion by viewing instead the “whole” of Buber as a Volkish and nationalist thinker (Ram 2015, p. 105). While I would argue that Ram’s conclusions amount to a strong overstatement, I agree that Buber’s affinity to Volkism remains a serious challenge to his national vision.How can one reconcile the two interpretations of the Zionism of Buber?—the revival of the Jewish people, which revitalizes “ancient”, “mystical” and even “mythical” powers, in the form of re-unity with the land; a communal people which existed by common past and blood ties on the one hand, and an ideal of humanistic and social solidarity with the neighbors, and integration in the Middle East, in the form of a bi-national state and a regional federation on the other hand.(cited in (Ram 2017, p. 279). Appears originally in Hebrew (Tal [1987] 2011, p. 29))
For Friedman, Buber’s distinction between the concept of nation and the concept of blood is thus not a qualitative one, but one that merely acknowledges the diversity of humankind without hierarchizing along “racial” lines (similar to Herder). Focusing also on Buber’s early thought, Dmitry Shumsky arrived at exactly the opposite conclusion: That Buber did view Judaism as superior to other cultures and indeed espoused a narrow ethnocentrism (Shumsky 2010). Even if this was the case, however, it still must be recalled that Buber later distanced himself with some remorse from his earlier writings21, a “turn” that Paul Mendes-Flohr has described in greater detail in his book From Mysticism to Dialogue (Mendes-Flohr 1989b) and essay “Martin Buber between Nationalism and Mysticism” (Mendes-Flohr 1980).Buber’s concept of “the community of blood” has often been identified with the type of racial mysticism prevalent in Germany at the time and later in cruder form incorporated into the myths of Nazism. […] There is, indeed, an element of biological vitalism and irrationalism in this concept of the “blood” that is bound to disquiet those who have lived through the Nazi era. But the differences, for all this, are more important than the similarities. Buber was not emphasizing the superiority of one people over another but the precious uniqueness of each. Buber wanted to know the unique potentialities and task of the Jewish people from within.
Indeed, whereas Buber rejected his earlier affinity with German nationalism, he continued to employ Volkish mythic terminology in articulating his later Zionist thought. Did Buber, then, simply exchange one nationalism for another, namely, his earlier German nationalism for his later Zionist nationalism?… from the very beginning the unique association between this people and this land was characterized by what was to be, by the intention that was to be realized. It was a consummation that could not be achieved by the people or the land on its own but only by the faithful cooperation of the two together and it was an association in which the land appeared not as a dead, passive object but as a living and active partner. Just as, to achieve fullness of life, the people needed the land, so the land needed the people, and the end which both were called upon to realize could only be reached by a living partnership.
We must construct a true human community [Gemeinschaft] in an utterly unromantic fashion, totally alert to the present and with the recalcitrant material of the historical present [Geschichtstag] ... It would be precipitous to designate as utopian that [endeavor] upon which we have yet to test our power. How much room God has allowed us, we can only know if we set ourselves to [the task]”(Cited in (Mendes-Flohr 1989a, pp. 162–63). Appears originally in German (Buber 1929, pp. 92–93)).24
3. Myth and Nationalisms
3.1. The Revival of Myth in Weimar
3.2. Buber on Myth and Judaism
The Aggadah was regarded as an idle play of fancy or a fictional composition of shallow parables, the Midrash as a collection of hairsplitting and uncreative commentaries, the Kabbalah as an absurd and grotesque numbers game; and Hasidism was barely known by name, or was disdainfully shrugged off as an unhealthy daydream.
3.3. Buber on Myth and Ethics
Here, Buber departs from Plato.40 Where the latter thinks of myth as a “noble lie” (Plato 2003, p. 105 [Book 3, 414 c]), a fiction that could be expressed more accurately in conceptual terms, Buber thinks of myth as a figure of truth that intervenes where truth fails to be articulated in conceptual language. For Buber, myth thus represents the true language of divine ethics that is itself riddled with ambivalence.41 Here, the categorical distinction made by Joseph Schwarz between “real-myth” and “human-myth” proves insufficient (Schwarz 1966, p. 242). Myth, then, touches precariously upon the problem of theopolitics.It implies that the experience which has taken place (not ‘been gained’) in factual encounters with evil in the world and the soul is directly embodied in myth, without making the detour through conceptual or semi-conceptual determinations. But, in addition, it is necessary for us, after passing through all the allegories and mystosophies, unscientific and scientific, of myth-interpretation, to be able and willing to accept the facts concerning human reality which are offered to us in the realm of myth.
3.4. Politics and Myth in Buber’s Thought
4. People and Land in Buber’s Theopolitics and Volkish Ideology
4.1. “The Kingdom of God” as the Kingdom of Dialogue
Perhaps because of its mythic character, Buber’s theopolitics, namely the anarchic vision of the Kingdom of God, has not been adequately recognized as following from Buber’s earlier work I and Thou (1923), where God (the eternal Thou) is also the voice that commands ethics. Through dialogue with God and fellow human beings (and non-human entities),54 the individual recognizes moral duties and ethical commandments as revealed in dialogue. One could therefore name the Kingdom of God the Kingdom of Dialogue. It is not only the individual who is expected to conduct the dialogue with God, but also the nation as a whole.It is the most visible appearance of that kingdom-dialectic which educated the Israelitish people to know history as the dialectic of an asking divinity and an answer-refusing, but nevertheless an answer-attempting humanity, the dialogue whose demand is an eschaton.
[…] the Kingship […] is not a productive calling. It is vain, but also bewildering and seditious, that men rule over man. Everyone is to pursue his own proper business, and the manifold fruitfulnesses will constitute a community over which, in order that it endure, no one [human] needs to rule—no one except God alone. […] The ‘commonwealth without government’ is thought of by the author or the redactor of the antimonarchic Book of Judges as commonwealth for which an invisible government is sufficient.
4.2. The Chosen Nation
Chosenness, in the 20th century, was transmuted into social-Darwinist ideas of selection. As a “superior race,” German ideologues claimed “the right” to rule over inferior species (Lehmann 1991, p. 267). Biblical chosenness turned into what Mosse called “election through blood” (Mosse [1964] 1981, p. 210). Volkish ideology rendered election a fact of nature, a privilege of power regardless of ethical and religious responsibilities.Bismarck’s German heirs became increasingly entangled in their lust for power and in the game of power politics. It was not religion that mattered, in their view, or God’s commands—much less did God call for solidarity with the underprivileged and the poor. What was important was power; or, to be more precise, German power: first in Central Europe, and then beyond.
Those chosen in the Bible, Buber argues, are not the greatest, most privileged, or those in power, but are precisely the unprivileged—those who have been left behind by nature, as it were:… not because of your eminence and importance has He chosen you—for you are of little consequence (Deut. 7:7) […] He has entrusted you with high office as a people (that, and not rank ...).
Buber thus rejects any kind of privilege or inherent quality in designating the national election of Israel; in place of the unconditional character of the Volkish natural “election through blood,” Buber stresses that the elected status of Israel is conditional:59 “Israel is elected only when it realizes its election” and “Israel is chosen only when it realizes the election by its life as a community” (Buber 2002a, p. 31). The “if” of election is related to a specific social task. This conditionality, coupled with the fact that election demands ethical piety within the political sphere, makes chosenness an ethical vocation.It is the weak and the humble who are chosen. By nature, it is the strong, those who can force their cause through, who are able and therefore chosen to perform the historical deeds. But in the Bible, it is often precisely the younger sons who are chosen, such as Abel, Jacob, Joseph, Moses, or David, and this choosing is accompanied by a rejection, often a very emphatic rejection, of the older sons; or, in other cases, those who are chosen were born out of wedlock, or of humble origin.
Buber’s theopolitical vision is not a narrow national vision of the redemption of the nation, but has a universal implication: God “wills that the peoples be truly brethren” (Buber 1960, p. 98). Thus, like Moses Hess, Buber perceives the nations as participating in the messianic task of redemption. No nation should be excluded, no contribution to the establishment of the Kingdom of God in the world is too small. The nations according to this universal vision (Buber 1973, pp. 34–35), will join Israel out of conviction, out of free will, and not out of coercion or political conquest.62 The universal vision of God’s kingship over the “human nation” comes to pass through the fulfilment of this Kingdom in Israel (Buber 1966, p. 206).This people had once been the first to respond to the One who spoke, where previously only the single individual had responded. It will not, after all its failures and even in the midst of its failures, cease to prepare itself anew for His word that is yet to come.
4.3. Fatherland vs. Eretz ha-Avot
The land of Israel is not a free gift nor a permanent property, but an assigned piece of land for the assigned vocation of an assigned people. Should the Israelites betray their ethical mission, they are destined to lose the land given to them.Now, then, if you will obey Me faithfully and keep My covenant, you shall be My treasured possession among all peoples. Indeed, all the earth is Mine, but you shall be to Me a Kingdom of Priests and a holy nation. These are the words that you [Moses] shall speak to the children of Israel.(Book of Exodus 19: 5–6; emphasis added)
Buber insists that the land is both the physical space and the ideal site of the ethical-utopian political vision: “[I]n Israel the earth is not merely, as in all other primitive peoples, peoples that preserve their primal energy [=Volkish idea], a living being [=Volkish idea], but it is also the partner in a moral, God-willed and God-guaranteed association” (Buber 1973, p. 14; my emphasis, brackets mine). Buber, as seen here, intentionally brought Volkish concepts to bear upon biblical myth, but only to distinguish these concepts once again sharply from Torat Israel (“not merely, [...] but also”). Buber thus construes Volkism as a primitive inclination that could be elevated by a biblical worldview that allowed for a transformation of the primitive into the ethical. In this sense, the “promised” land stands as a moral vision of anticipated political-social order that has yet to be realized in a designated and concrete place upon earth. Only on its own land can the people exercise its agency and accept—or resume—the work of building a theopolitical regime. Rather than ethnic roots, it is the ethical bond, a bond of duty, that establishes, for Buber, a nation’s right to the soil. Yet, this bond, as Buber demonstrates awareness of, lacks the mythic permanence of the Volkish image of the land, for it lacks Volkism’s tenet of unconditional inheritance.God grants no security. If the house wherein His name dwells has become a robbers’ den and there is no repentance, then it will be given over to destruction.... God, the King of Israel, leaves His throne and abandons it to destruction because Israel has not taken His kingdom seriously. It has known only the King’s protective power and not submission of its own lived communal life to the truth of the King’s covenant. But Israel is elected only when it realizes its election.(Buber 2002a, p. 31; my emphasis)
5. Ethicizing Myth: Hasidism and the Purification of Myth
“Nevertheless, it is to myth that Judaism owed its inmost cohesiveness in times of danger. Not Joseph Karo but Isaac Luria in the sixteenth century, and not the Gaon of Vilna but the Baal Shem in the eighteenth century, truly consolidated and demarcated Judaism by raising a folk-religion to a power in Israel and renewing the people’s personality from the roots of its myth”.
Nationalism, for Buber, was symptomatic of self-isolation and, ultimately, of a severing of all ties to the world. Despite its roots in nature, nationalism rejects the world, because it fails to see the world as sacred and redeemable. Hasidism, in Buber’s interpretation, restores the severed ties to the world and to other nations. It hallows the world and can thus effectively harness the secular-nationalist energy of Zionism. How specifically can Hasidism activate this potential in the fight against nationalism? How does one fight myth with myth?Here in Hasidism we have something close to us in time, and its off-shoots reach into our very age. Hasidism is a great revelation of spirit and life in which the nation appears to be connected by an inner tie with the world, with the soul, and with God. Only through such a contact will it be possible to guard Zionism against following the way of the nationalism of our age, which by demolishing the bridges which connect it with the world, is destroying its own value and its right to exist.(Buber 1966, p. 218; my emphasis)
Since good and bad in the world are entangled with one another, their meanings at times are elusive, bewildering and deceptive. This reality renders the work of clarification a life-long task, which unfolds only through sincere introspection and openness to dialogue with others. Sorting out good from bad is a kind of decision (Ent-scheidung)—a moral purification that is demanded of the individual in Hasidism.70 However, tradition itself needs purifying, especially in times of crisis in which ethical messages can become illegible or be purposely misused.71The Torah, the teaching of Israel, is a teaching of distinction. […] so man is bidden by revelation to distinguish: between God and Idols, between true and false prophets, between pure and impure, between good and evil, between sacred and profane; […] and the destiny of man, his destiny in the most exact sense of the term, that of the individual and that of the totality, depends upon the right distinction. […] the distinction that is taught in the Torah means decision, a decision in which man decides concerning himself(Buber 1966, pp. 72–73; my emphasis).69
In these few lines, Buber suggests that religious symbols, some very powerful signs, can be depleted of their ethical meaning. However, even as their original religious meaning erodes, symbols remain powerful. When they become detached from their ethical meanings, it is upon the “man who devotes himself” to renew “the strength of the origin saved for further present existence” (Buber 1966, p. 153). Buber’s theopolitics attempts precisely that. Buber takes a decisive political action with regard to Volkish myths, not by trying to abolish them—since they cannot be truly abolished—but by decontaminating and purifying them.Every symbol is always in danger of changing from a real sign sent into life into a spiritual and unbinding image, every sacrament of changing from a bodily event between above and below into a flat experience on the “religious” plane. Only through the man who devotes himself is the strength of the origin saved for further present existence.
6. Conclusions: Myth-Activism and Myth as a Figure of Truth
Funding
Acknowledgments
Conflicts of Interest
References
- Almog, Shmuel. 1991. Judaism as Illness: Antisemitic Stereotype as self-image. History of European Ideas 13: 793–804. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Almog, Shmuel, and Michael Hed, eds. 1991. The Idea of Election in Israel and the Nations: Essay Collection. Jerusalem: Shazar Center. [Google Scholar]
- Altshuler, Mor. 2006. The Messianic Secret of Hasidism. Leiden: Brill, pp. 324–28. [Google Scholar]
- Aschheim, Steven E. 1992. The Nietzsche Legacy in Germany, 1890–1990. Berkeley: University of California Press. [Google Scholar]
- Aschheim, Steven E. 2007. Beyond the Border: The German-Jewish Legacy Abroad. Princeton: Princeton University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Assmann, Jan. 2010. The Price of Monotheism. Translated by Robert Savage. Stanford: Stanford University Press. First published 2003. [Google Scholar]
- Assmann, Aleida. 1998. Mythos. In Handwörterbuch Religionswissenschaftlicher Grundbegriffe IV, hg. Edited by Hubert Cancik, Burkhard Gladigow and Karl H. Kohl. Stuttgart: Kohlhammer, pp. 179–200. [Google Scholar]
- Avnon, Dan. 1993. The ‘Living Center’ of Martin Buber’s Political Theory. Political Theory 21: 55–77. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Bambach, Charles. 2013. Weimar Philosophy and the Crisis of Historical Thinking. In Weimar Thought: A Contested Legacy. Edited by Peter E. Gordon and John P. McCormick. Princton and Oxford: Princeton University Press, pp. 133–49. [Google Scholar]
- Batnitzky, Leora. 2000. On the Truth of History or the History of Truth: Rethinking Rosenzweig via Strauss. Jewish Studies Quarterly 7: 223–51. [Google Scholar]
- Batnitzky, Leora. 2006. Revelation and Neues Denken: Rethinking Buber and Rosenzweig on the Law. In New Perspectives on Martin Buber. Edited by Michael Zank. Tubingen: Mohr Sieback, pp. 149–64. [Google Scholar]
- Berlin, Isaiah. 1980. Vico and Herder: Two Studies in the History of Ideas. London: Chatto & Windus. [Google Scholar]
- Berlin, Isaiah. 2005. Herder and Historical Criticism. Berlin: Isaiah Berlin Literary Trust. [Google Scholar]
- Biale, David. 1979. Gershom Scholem: Kabbalah and Counter-History. Cambridge: Harvard University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Biale, David. 2007. Blood and Belief: The Circulation of a Symbol between Jews and Christians. Berkley: University of California Press. [Google Scholar]
- Biemann, Asher D. 2006. Aesthetic Education in Martin Buber: Jewish Renaissance and the Artist. In New Perspectives on Martin Buber. Edited by Michael Zank. Tübingen: Mohr Siebeck. [Google Scholar]
- Biemann, Asher D. 2009. Inventing New Beginnings: On the Idea of Renaissance in Modern Judaism. Stanford: Stanford University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Biemann, Asher D. 2018a. “Vae Victis!”: Antisemitism as Self-Victimization (and What Spinoza Knew about It). In Charlottesville 2017: The Legacy of Race and Inequity. Edited by Louis P. Nelson and Claudrena N. Harold. Charlottesville: University of Virginia Press, pp. 50–59. [Google Scholar]
- Biemann, Asher D. 2018b. Cassirer and the Myth of the State, Unpublished manuscript, last modified Juli 3. Microsoft Word File.
- Bourel, Dominique. 2017. Martin Buber: Was es heißt, ein Mensch zu sein. Biografie. Übersetzt von Horst Brühmann. Gütersloh: Gütersloher Verlagshaus. [Google Scholar]
- Braatz, Werner E. 1974. The Volkish Ideology and Anti-Semitism in Germany. Yivo Annual of Jewish Social Science 15: 166–87. [Google Scholar]
- Breslauer, Daniel. 2016. Martin Buber’s Myth of Zion: National Education or Counter-Education? Studies in Philosophy and Education 35: 493–511. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Brody, Samuel Hayim. 2015. Is Theopolitics an Antipolitics? In Dialogue as a Trans-Disciplinary Concept. Martin Buber’s Philosophy of Dialogue and its Contemporary Reception. Edited by Paul Mendes-Flohr. Berlin: De Gruyter, pp. 61–88. [Google Scholar]
- Brody, Samuel Hayim. 2018. Martin Buber’s Theopolitics. Indiana: Indiana University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Buber, Martin. 1916. Die Geschichten des Rabbi Nachman. Leipzig: Oscar Brandstetter. First published 1906. [Google Scholar]
- Buber, Martin. 1917. Ereignisse und Begegnungen. Leipzig: Insel. [Google Scholar]
- Buber, Martin. 1929. Einladung zu einer sozialistischen Aussprache in der Pfingstwoche 1928 Heppenheim a.d. Bergstrasse. In Sozialismus aus dem Glauben: Verhandlungen der sozialistischen Tagung in Heppenheim am Bergstrasse. Zurich: Rotapfel. [Google Scholar]
- Buber, Martin. 1952. Good and Evil: Two Interpretations. New York: Charles Scribner’s Sons. [Google Scholar]
- Buber, Martin. 1956. The Tales of Rabbi Nachman. Translated by Maurice Friedman. New York: Horizon Press. [Google Scholar]
- Buber, Martin. 1959. Teuda VeYeud: Essays on Judaism and Jewish Affairs. Jerusalem: The Zionist Library, vol. I. [Google Scholar]
- Buber, Martin. 1960. The Prophetic Faith. Translated by Carlyle Witton-Davies. New York: Happer and Row. [Google Scholar]
- Buber, Martin. 1963. The Writings of Martin Buber. Edited and Introduced by Will Herberg. New York: Meridian Books. [Google Scholar]
- Buber, Martin. 1966. The Origin and Meaning of Haisidism. Edited and Translated by Maurice Friedman. New York: Harper & Row. [Google Scholar]
- Buber, Martin. 1967. Kingship of God. Translated by Richard Scheimann. London: George Allen and Unwin Ltd. [Google Scholar]
- Buber, Martin. 1970. I and Thou. Translated, Prologue and Notes by Walter Kaufmann. New York: Charles Scribner’s Sons. [Google Scholar]
- Buber, Martin. 1973. On Zion: The History of an Idea. Forward by Nahum N. Glatzer. Originally published as Israel and Palastine—The History of an Idea in 1952. London: Horovitz Publishing. [Google Scholar]
- Buber, Martin. 1982. On the Bible: Eighteen Studies. Edited by Nahum N. Glatzer. Introduction by Harold Bloom. New York: Schocken Books. [Google Scholar]
- Buber, Martin. 1983. A Land of Two Peoples: Martin Buber on Jews and Arabs. Edited with Commentary Paul R. Mendes-Flohr. New York: Oxford University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Buber, Martin. 1984. Teuda VeYeud: People and Universe: Essays on Contemporary Affairs. Jerusalem: The Zionist Library, vol. II. [Google Scholar]
- Buber, Martin. 1995. On Judaism. Edited by Nahum N. Glatzer. Forward by Rodger Kamenetz. New York: Schocken Books. [Google Scholar]
- Buber, Martin. 1997. Israel and the World: Essays in a Time of Crisis. New York: Syracuse. [Google Scholar]
- Buber, Martin. 2002a. The Martin Buber Reader: Essential Writings. Edited by Asher D. Biemann. New York: Palgrave Macmillan. [Google Scholar]
- Buber, Martin. 2002b. The Legend of the Baal-Shem. Translated by Maurice Friedmann. London and New York: Routlrdge. [Google Scholar]
- Buber, Martin. 2016. Hasidism and Modern Man. Edited and Translated by Maurice Friedmann. Introduction by David Biale. Princeton: Princeton University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Bultmann, Rudolf. 1989. New Testament and Mythology and other Basic Writings. Selected, Edited and Translated by Schubert M. Ogden. Philadelphia: Fortress Press. [Google Scholar]
- Caputo, John. 2000. People of God, People of Being: The Theological Presuppositions of Heidegger’s Path of Thought. In Appropriating Heidegger. Edited by James E. James Falconer and Mark A. Wrathall. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Cassirer, Ernst. 1946. The Myth of the State. Foreword by Charles W. Hendel. New Haven: Yale University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Chapoutot, Johann. 2016. Greeks, Romans, Germans: How the Nazis Usurped Europe’s Classical Past. Translated by Richard R. Nybakken. Oakland: University of California Press. [Google Scholar]
- De Oliveira, Manuel Duarte. 1996. Passion for Land and Volk: Martin Buber and Neo Romanticism. The Leo Baeck Institute Year Book 41: 239–60. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Etkes, Immanuel. 2002. The Gaon of Vilna: The Man and His Image. Translated by Jeffrey M. Green. Berkeley: University of California Press. [Google Scholar]
- Feller, Yaniv. 2013. From Aher to Marcion: Martin Buber’s Understanding of Gnosis. Jewish Studies Quarterly 20: 374–97. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Friedman, Maurice. 1988. Martin Buber’s Life and Work. Detroit: Wayne State University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Gordon, Adi, ed. 2008. Brith Shalom and Bi-National Zionism: The ‘Arab Question’ as a Jewish Question. Jerusalem: Carmel. [Google Scholar]
- Groiser, David. 2013. Einleitung. In Martin Buber Werkausgabe: Mythos Und Mystik: Frühe Religionswissenschaftliche Schriften. Edited, Forwarded and Commented by David Groiser. Gütersloh: Gütersloher Verlagshaus, pp. 11–60. [Google Scholar]
- Guttmann, Yehiel M. H. 1929. Eretz Israel be-Midrash ve-Talmud. Berlin: Reuven Mas. [Google Scholar]
- Hadad, Yemima. 2017. Fruits of Forgetfulness: Nationalism and Politics in the Philosophy of Martin Buber and Martin Heidegger. In Heidegger and Jewish Thought. Edited by Elad Lapidot and Micha Brumlik. London and New York: Rowman & Littlefield International, pp. 201–20. [Google Scholar]
- Halamish, Moshe. 1999. An Introduction to Kabbalah. Translated by Ruth Bar-ilan, and Ora Wiskind-Elper. Albany: State University of New York Press. [Google Scholar]
- Herf, Jeffrey. 1986. Reactionary Modernism: Technology, Culture, and Politics in Weimar and the Third Reich. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. First Published 1984. [Google Scholar]
- Hever, Hannan. 2016. The Politics of Form of the Hassidic Tale. Dibur: Literary Journal 2: 57–73. [Google Scholar]
- Hotam, Yotam. 2007. Modern Gnosis and Zionism: The Crisis of Culture, Life Philosophy and Jewish National Thought. Jerusalem: Magnes Press. [Google Scholar]
- Huss, Boaz. 2008. Martin Buber’s Introduction to The Stories of Rabbi Nachman and the Genealogy of Jewish Mysticism. In By the Well: Studies in Jewish Philosophy and Halakhic Thought Presented to Gerald J. Blidstein. Edited by Uri Ehrlich, Howard Kreisel and Daniel J. Lasker. Beer Sheva: Ben Gurion University Press, pp. 97–121. [Google Scholar]
- Jacobson, Yoram. 1985. Hasidic Thought. Tel Aviv: Misrad HaBitakhon. [Google Scholar]
- Jay, Martin. 1976. Politics of Translation: Siegfried Kracauer and Walter Benjamin on the Buber-Rosenzweig Bible. Leo Baeck Institute Yearbook 21: 3–24. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Jobani, Yuval. 2016. The Lure of Heresy: A Philosophical Typology of Hebrew Secularism in the First Half of the Twentieth Century. The Journal of Jewish Thought and Philosophy 24: 95–121. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Jospe, Raphael. 1994. The Concept of the Chosen People: An Interpretation. Judaism 43: 127–48. [Google Scholar]
- Kaplan, Gregory. 2014. Power and Israel in Martin Buber’s Critique of Carl Schmitt’s Political Theology. In Judaism Liberalism and Political Theology. Edited by Randi Rashkover and Martin Kavka. Bloomington: Indiana University Press, pp. 166–77. [Google Scholar]
- Kaufmann, Yehezkel. 1951. The Bible and Mythological Polytheism. Journal of Biblical Literature 70: 179–97. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Kenaan, Hagi, Shmuel Rottem, and Dana Barnea. 2012. Heidegger in Jerusalem: An Unknown Chapter in the Formation of a Local Philosophy. Theory and Criticism 40: 35–66. [Google Scholar]
- Keren, Michael. 1983. Ben Gurion and the Intellectuals: Power, Knowledge, and Charisma. DeKalb: Northern Illinois University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Koren, Israel. 2010. The Mystery of the Earth. Mysticism and Hasidism in the Thought of Martin Buber. Leiden: BRILL. [Google Scholar]
- Kosman, Admiel. 2007. Notes and Explanations to Martin Buber‘s ‘I and Thou’. In Judaism: Essence Genius, Nature: Sefer Rivka. Edited by Pedaya Haviva, Meir Ephraim and Horwitz Rivka. Beer Sheva: Ben-Gurion University Press, pp. 511–24. [Google Scholar]
- Kosman, Admiel. 2013. Introduction to Buber’s Teachings. In I and Thou. Translated by Aharon Flashman. Jerusalem: Mosad Bialik, pp. 160–231. [Google Scholar]
- Kosman, Admiel. 2017. Torat ha-Shem Temima: Hasidim and Mitnagdim on Limud Torah. In The Baal Shem Tov: The Man Who Came from the Woods. Edited by Roee Horen. Rishon LeZion: Miskal—Yedioth Aharonoth, pp. 214–23. [Google Scholar]
- Krochmalnik, Daniel. 1997. Neue Tafeln: Nietzsche und die Jüdischen Counter-History. In Jüdischer Nietzscheanismus. Edited by Werner Stegmaier and Daniel Krochmalnik. Berlin and New York: de Gruyter, pp. 53–81. [Google Scholar]
- Lamm, Norman. 1999. The Religious Thought of Hasidism: Text and Commentary. New York: Yeshiva Universty Press, pp. 267–70. [Google Scholar]
- Lapidot, Elad. 2016. Heidegger’s Tshuva? Heidegger Studies 32: 33–52. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Lebovic, Nitzan. 2008. The Jerusalem School: The Theopolitical Hour. New German Critique 105: 97–120. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Lebow, Richard Ned. 2012. The Politics and Ethics of Identity: In Search of Ourselves. New York: Cambridge University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Lehmann, Hartmut. 1991. The Germans as a Chosen People: Old Testament Themes in German Nationalism. German Studies Review 14: 261–73. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Lesch, Charles H. T. 2018. Theopolitics Contra Political Theology: Martin Buber’s Biblical Critique of Carl Schmitt. American Political Science Review, 1–14. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Levy, Zeev. 1988. De-Mythologization or Re-Mythologization. Bar-Illan 22–23: 205–27. [Google Scholar]
- Loewy, Michael. 2017. The Romantic Socialism of Gustav Landauer. In Jews and Leftist Politics: Judaism, Israel, Antisemitism and Gender. Edited by Jack Jacobs. New York: Cambridge University Press, pp. 252–66. [Google Scholar]
- Lorberbaum, Menachem. 2001. Politics and the Limits of the Law: Secularizing the Political in Medieval Jewish Thought. Stanford: Stanford University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Lunn, Eugene. 1973. Prophet of Community: The Romantic Socialism of Gustav Landauer. Berkeley: University of California Press. [Google Scholar]
- Lutzhöft, Hans-Jürgen. 1971. Der Nordische Gedanke in Deutschland, 1920–1940. Stuttgart: Ernst Klett Verlag. [Google Scholar]
- Luz, Ehud. 1995. Buber’s Hermeneutics: The Road to the Revival of the Collective Memory and Religious Faith. Modern Judaism 15: 69–93. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Mali, Joseph. 2012. Between Myth and History: The Legacy of Livy. In Culture, Memory and History: Essays in Honor of Anita Shapira. Edited by Uri S. Cohen and Meir Chazan. Jerusalem: Zalman Shazar, pp. 71–91. [Google Scholar]
- Mendes-Flohr, Paul. 1980. Martin Buber between Nationalism and Mysticism. Iyyun 29: 71–92. [Google Scholar]
- Mendes-Flohr, Paul. 1984. Fin-de-siècle Orientalism, the Ostjuden, and the Aesthetics of Jewish Self-Affirmation. Studies in Contemporary Jewry 1: 96–139. [Google Scholar]
- Mendes-Flohr, Paul. 1989a. Nationalism as a Spiritual Sensibility: The Philosophical Suppositions of Buber’s Hebrew Humanism. The Journal of Religion 69: 155–68. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Mendes-Flohr, Paul. 1989b. From Mysticism to Dialogue: Martin Buber’s Transformation of German Social Thought. Detroit: Wayne State University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Mendes-Flohr, Paul. 1991. Divided Passions: Jewish Intellectuals and the Experience of Modernity. Detroit: Wayne State University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Mendes-Flohr, Paul. 1997. Zarathustra’s Apostle: Martin Buber and the Jewish Renaissance. In Nietzsche and Jewish Culture. Edited by Jacob. J. Golomb. London and New York: Routledge. [Google Scholar]
- Mendes-Flohr, Paul. 2008. The Kingdom of God: Martin Buber’s Critique of Messianic Politics. Behemoth: A Journal on Civilisation 1: 26–38. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Mendes-Flohr, Paul. 2014. Martin Buber and Martin Heidegger in Dialogue. The Journal of Religion 94: 2–25. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Mendes-Flohr, Paul, and Zeev Gries. 1988. Introduction. In The Tales of Rabbi Nachman. Edited by Martin Buber. Translated by Maurice Friedman. Atlantic Highlands: Humanities Press International, pp. ix–xxviii. [Google Scholar]
- Mosse, George L. 1981. The Crisis of the German Ideology. New-York: Schocken Books. First published 1964. [Google Scholar]
- Mosse, George L. 1987. Germans and Jews: Right, the Left and the Search for a “Third Force” in Pre Nazi Germany. Detroit: Wayne State University Press. First published 1970. [Google Scholar]
- Ohana, David. 2018. Nietzsche and Jewish Political Theology. New-York: Routledge. [Google Scholar]
- Oppenheimer, Benjamin. 1967. Monotheism in M. Buber’s Thought. Molad 1: 207–12. [Google Scholar]
- Oronzo, Theresa. 1994. Die Platon-Rezeption in Deutschland um 1933. In Die Besten Geister der Nation: Philosophie und Nationalsozialismus. Edited by IIse Erika Korotin and Gerwin Klinger. Wien: Picus Verlag. [Google Scholar]
- Perry, Marvin, and Frederick M. Schweitzer. 2002. Antisemitism: Myth and Hate from Antiquity to the Present. New York: Palgrave Macmillan. [Google Scholar]
- Perry, Marvin, Myrna Chase, James R. Jacob, Margaret C. Jacob, Jonathan W. Daly, and Theodore H. Von Laue. 2016. Western Civilization: Ideas, Politics and Society since 1400. Boston: Cengage Learning. [Google Scholar]
- Piekarz, Mendel. 1998. The Descent of the Zaddik to Geheynom and his Descent from his Spiritual Rung in this World (chapter 7). In The Beginning of Hasidism: Ideological Trends in Drush and Musar Literature. Jerusalem: Mosad Bialik, pp. 280–302. First published 1978. [Google Scholar]
- Plato. 2003. The Republic. Cambridge Texts in the History of Political Thought. Edited by G. R. F. Ferrari. Translated by Tom Griffith. Cambridge and New-York: Cambridge University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Pollock, Benjamin. 2014. Franz Rosenzweig’s Conversions: World Denial and World Redemption. Bloomington and Indianapolis: Indiana University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Ram, Uri. 2015. The Return of Martin Buber: National and Social Thought in Israel from Martin Buber to the Neo-Buberians. Tel Aviv: Resling. [Google Scholar]
- Ram, Uri. 2017. Buber between Left and Right. In Jews and Leftist Politics. Edited by Jack Jacobs. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 267–88. [Google Scholar]
- Rash, Felicity. 2012. German Images of the Self and the Other: Nationalist, Colonialist and Anti-Semitic Discourse 1871–1918. New-York: Palgrave Macmillan. [Google Scholar]
- Ratzabi, Shalom. 2002. Between Zionism and Judaism: The Radical Circle in Brith Shalom 1925–1933. Leiden: Brill. [Google Scholar]
- Ratzabi, Shalom. 2004a. Zionism as Theopolitics and the a-Naturalistic Character of Jewish Nationalism: Commentary on Martin Buber’s National Thought and its Origins. Iyunim BiTkumat Israel: Studies in Zionism, the Yishuv and the State of Israel 14: 97–129. [Google Scholar]
- Ratzabi, Shalom. 2004b. Race, Nation and Judaism in M. M. Buber’s and Z. Jabotinsky’s Thought: A Comparative Study. In The Eye of the Storm: Essays on Ze’ev Jabotinsky. Edited by Avi Bareli and Pinhas Ginossar. Beer Sheva: Ben-Gurion University Press, pp. 121–58. [Google Scholar]
- Ratzabi, Shalom. 2011. Anarchism in Zion: Between Martin Buber and Aharon David Gordon. Tel-Aviv: Am Oved. In Anarchism in Zion: Between Martin Buber and Aharon David Gordon. Tel-Aviv: Am Oved. [Google Scholar]
- Schaefer, Yoav. 2017. Between Political Theology and Theopolitics: Martin Buber’s. Kingship of God, Modern Judaism—A Journal of Jewish Ideas and Experience 37: 231–55. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Schatz, Rivka. 1960. The Essence of the Zaddik in Hasidism: Reflections on the doctrine of the Zaddik of Rebbe Elimelech of Lizhensk. Molad 18: 365–77. [Google Scholar]
- Schmidt, Christoph. 2016. Martin Buber (1878–1965): The Theopolitical Hour. In Markers of Jewish Modernity: Thinkers, Artists, Leaders and the World they Made. Edited by Jacques Picard, Jacques Revel, Michael P. Steinberg and Idith Zertal. Translated by Samuel Hayim Brody. Princeton: Princeton University Press, pp. 187–203. [Google Scholar]
- Scholem, Gershom. 1976. On Jews and Judaism in Crisis: Selected Essays. New York: Schocken Books. [Google Scholar]
- Schwartz, Regina. 1997. The Curse of Cain: The Violent Legacy of Monotheism. Chicago and London: The University of Chicago Press. [Google Scholar]
- Schwarz, Joseph. 1966. Language, Myth, Art: Studies in Modern Jewish Thought. Jerusalem: Schocken. [Google Scholar]
- Schwarz, Joseph. 1978. From Myth to Revelation. Tel Aviv: Bar-Illan University & Hakibutz Hameukhad. [Google Scholar]
- Shapira, Avraham. 1993. Buber’s Attachment to Herder and German Volkism. Studies in Zionism 14: 1–30. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Shonkoff, Sam Berrin. 2018. Sacramental Existence: Embodiment in Martin Buber’s Philosophical and Hasidic Writings. Ph.D. dissertation, University of Chicago, Chicago, IL, USA. [Google Scholar]
- Shumsky, Dmitry. 2010. Between Prague and Jerusalem: Prague Zionists and the Origins of the Idea of Binational State in Palestine. Jerusalem: Shazar Center & Leo Baeck. [Google Scholar]
- Silberstein, J. Laurence. 1989. Martin Buber’s Social and Religious Thought: Alienation and the Quest for Meaning. New York and London: New York University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Simon, Akiba Ernst. 1966. Buber or Ben-Gurion? New Outlook 9: 9–17. [Google Scholar]
- Simon, Akiba Ernst. 1973. The Line of Demarcation: Nationalism, Zionism and the Jewish-Arab Conflict in Martin Buber’s thought and Political Activity. Givat Haviva: The Center for Arab Studies. [Google Scholar]
- Simon, Josef. 1997. Die eine Wahrheit und die fremde Vernunft: Volk und Judentum bei Nietzsche. In Jüdischer Nietzscheanismus. Berlin and New York: de Gruyter, pp. 3–15. [Google Scholar]
- Stackelberg, Roderick. 1981. Idealism Debased: From Volkish Ideology to National Socialism. Ohio: The Kent State University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Statman, Daniel, and Avi Sagie. 1986. Relationship between Religion and Morality in Buber’s Though. Daat: A Journal of Jewish Philosophy & Kabbalah 17: 97–118. [Google Scholar]
- Steigmann-Gall, Richard. 2003. The Holy Reich: Nazi Conceptions of Christianity 1919–1945. New York: Cambridge University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Sufrin, Claire E. 2012. On Myth, History, and the Study of Hasidism: Martin Buber and Gershom Scholem. In Encountering the Medieval in Modern Jewish Thought. Leiden, The Netherlands: Brill. [Google Scholar]
- Sufrin, Claire E. 2013. History, Myth, and Divine Dialogue in Martin Buber’s Biblical Commentaries. The Jewish Quarterly Review 103: 74–100. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Susser, Bernard. 1977. Ideological Multivalence: Martin Buber and the German Volkish Tradition. Political Theory 5: 75–96. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Tal, Uriel. 2011. Myth and Reason in Contemporary Jewry. Tel Aviv: HaKibbutz HaMeuchad. First published 1987. [Google Scholar]
- Talmon, Jacob. 1973. Romanticism and Rebellion: Europe 1815–1845. Tel Aviv: Am Oved. [Google Scholar]
- Tishby, Isaiah. 1967. The Messianic Idea and Messianic Trends in the Growth of Hasidism. Zion 32: 1–45. [Google Scholar]
- Urban, Martina. 2004. Retelling Biblical Mythos Through the Hasidic Tale: Buber’s “Saul and David” and the Question of Leadership. Modern Judaism 24: 59–78. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Weiss, Joseph. 1951. Beginnings of Hasidim. Zion 17: 46–105. [Google Scholar]
- Weiss, Yfaat. 2004. Central European Ethnonationalism and Zionist Binationalism. Jewish Social Studies 11: 93–117. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Whitman, James. 2018. Hitler’s American Model: The United States and the Making of Nazi race Law. Princeton: Princeton University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Winter, Julie M. 1998. Luther Bible Research in the Context of Volkish Nationalism in the Twentieth Century. New York: Peter Lang. [Google Scholar]
- Wolf, Eric R. 1999. Envisioning Power: Ideologies of Dominance and Crisis. Berkeley: University of California Press. [Google Scholar]
- Wurgaft, Lewis D. 1977. The Activists: Kurt Hiller and the Politics of Action on the German Left 1914–1933. The American Philosophical Society 67: 5–111. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Young, Julian. 2006. Nietzsche’s Philosophy of Religion. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Ziderman, Asaf. 2018. Chaos, Abgrund, and Wirbel: On Buber’s Notion of Ambivalence, August 27, Unpublished Manuscript. Last modified August 27. Microsoft Word file.
- Ziolkowski, Theodore. 1970. Der Hunger nach dem Mythos: Zur seelischen Gastronomie der Deutschen in den Zwanziger Jahren. In Die sogenannten Zwanziger Jahre. Edited by Reinhold R. Grimm and Jost Hermand. Berlin: Bad Homburg, pp. 169–201. [Google Scholar]
1 | My work on theopolitics aligns with the work of Shalom Ratzabi (2011) and Samuel Brody (2018), extending their basic arguments beyond Buber’s Biblical exegesis towards his understanding of Hasidism. I suggest defining theopolitics as a messianic vision pursuing the realization of the Kingdom of God in the world, where human sovereignty is renounced in favor of direct divine sovereignty. The members of this community of God practice non-dominance in their social-political order and accept the divine law (for Buber: Dialogical ethics) over their own free will in all their political and social affairs. |
2 | The term ‘activism’ was coined in 1915 by Kurt Hiller and “paralleled those of literary expressionism in Germany.” It was an “aesthetic movement that provided the initial impetus for the activist cause” (Wurgaft 1977, p. 11). Asher Biemann indicates that Buber objected to the kind of activism Kurt Hiller and his circle advocated. Buber considered their “spiritual activism” romanticist, and criticized what he saw as “undirected activism.” He distanced himself from what he saw as “mere literature” that involves no real doing (Biemann 2006, p. 105). For more on Kurt Hiller’s activism, see (Wurgaft 1977). I use the term ‘activism’ here to indicate that Buber’s political engagement was not about mere action (speeches, publications, protests, political initiations, etc.). Quite to the contrary: Myth-activism indicates that Buber’s intellectual action aimed to change the prevailing political inclinations by correcting the underlying myths. Reform of political life, to Buber, was a fundamentally literary task. For more on literature and politics, especially the politics of the Hasidic tale, see (Hever 2016). I thank Hannan Hever for the inspiring and influential conversations on literature and politics. |
3 | In the original quote, Mosse used the term ‘Negro,’ which was common at that time. |
4 | There are indications that Volkish thought was also adopted by left-wing humanist and universalist Gustav Landauer, as described by Eugene Lunn (1973) and more recently by Michael Loewy (2017). Landauer’s own estrangement from Judaism, as indicated by Paul Mendes-Flohr, was a rebellion against the bourgeois order. It was in Buber’s Hasidic tales that Landauer found a Judaism corresponding to the value of the working people and expressing his association with the proletariat (Mendes-Flohr 1984, p. 127). |
5 | Buber initially embraced the cause of World War I. For more on this affair and on Buber’s political “turn,” see: (Mendes-Flohr 1980; 1989b, pp. 93–126). See also: Kriegsbuber (Bourel 2017, pp. 208–12). |
6 | On the Volkish movement, see also: (Perry and Schweitzer 2002, pp. 88–93), as well as (Perry et al. 2016, p. 600). |
7 | Like sickness, forgetfulness was also an appealing narrative to intellectuals at the fin de siècle. Nietzsche and Heidegger used it explicitly; I argue that Buber had an implicit notion of forgetfulness. For more on forgetfulness and nationalism in Buber’s and Heidegger’s thought, see my essay: “Fruits of Forgetfulness” (Hadad 2017). There, I discuss the term Dialogvergessenheit and compare it to Heidegger’s Seinsvergessenheit. The term ‘forgetfulness’ appears in Leora Batnitzky’s insightful essays in which she compares Buber with Heidegger in illuminating Buber’s perception of history and his disposition towards the Halakha (Batnitzky 2000, 2006). Ehud Luz also mentions forgetfulness in Buber’s hermeneutics (Luz 1995, pp. 80–81). On the intellectual exchange and personal relationship between Buber and Heidegger after World War II, see: (Mendes-Flohr 2014). On Heidegger’s reception in Jerusalem, see: (Kenaan et al. 2012). A fuller account on forgetfulness will appear in my dissertation. |
8 | See also idem Vico and Herder (Berlin 1980). |
9 | E.g., the Zionist Blau-Weiss youth movement as an imitation of the German youth movement Wandervögel (Mosse [1970] 1987, p. 97). Mosse highlights that Buber was a friend and associate of Eugen Diederichs, who was a prominent Volkish publisher cultivating theories of return to the soil and oriental mysticism (Mosse [1970] 1987, p. 88). See also Mendes-Flohr (1984). More on Buber’s connection to the Zionist Youth Movement in “Herman Gerson and the ‘Work Folk’” (Friedman 1988, Part II, pp. 142–54). |
10 | Buber elaborates this idea in his essay “The Spirit of the Orient and Judaism” (1912) (Buber 1995, pp. 56–78). |
11 | The terms ‘contamination’ and ‘purification’ were prevalent in Volkish Kulturkritik and went through anti-Semitic politicization. Lagarde and others called for the “Purification” of the German soul and blood (Braatz 1974, pp. 169, 181–82, 185; Stackelberg 1981, pp. 4–5). Buber, I argue, uses the idea of purification in a Hasidic theological rather than Volkish context, as I explain in the fourth section of this essay. |
12 | Buber’s doctoral thesis was entitled Beiträge zur Geschichte des Individuationsproblems: Nicolaus von Cues und Jakob Böhme (1904). |
13 | Buber made a distinction between religion (the organizing principle) and religiosity (the creative force) in his essay “Jewish Religiosity” (Buber 1995, pp. 79–94). In addition to Georg Simmel, Buber testified that A. D. Gordon was to him a “true teacher” in matters of religiosity. See more about that in (Jobani 2016). |
14 | David Biale and Daniel Krochmalnik indicated that Buber’s Hasidism and his understanding of subterranean “counter-history” follows Berdyczewski and Nietzsche. In the same way that Berdyczewski considered the Hasidim “Dionysian” people who fought against sclerotic rabbinism, Buber fought against rabbinic religion with Hasidic religiosity. In Hasidism, Berdyczewski saw the return of a vital disposition. His Zaddikim signified the overman in a Nietzschean Zarathustric way. Buber, claims Krochmalnik, holds a similar point of view (Biale 1979, pp. 37–47; Krochmalnik 1997, p. 59; Buber 1995, pp. 79–94). |
15 | See also: (Jay 1976, p. 17). |
16 | This notwithstanding, Susser argues that by adopting this terminology Buber departed from the same ideas: Whereas in Volkish ideology ideas such as Gemeinschaft, leadership, etc. became coercive, they remained in Buber’s thought voluntary. He speaks of a “mirror-image” between Buber and the Volkish thought, where the same terminology conveys two divergent dispositions. Susser refers to these contradicting tendencies in Buber’s thought as “multivalent tendencies.” |
17 | See also: (Ram 2015, p. 100). |
18 | See also his essay in English: (Ram 2017). |
19 | Asaf Ziderman dealt with ambivalence as a philosophical notion and disposition in Buber’s thought in his essay “Chaos, Abgrund, and Wirbel: On Buber’s Notion of Ambivalence” (Ziderman 2018). I thank him for sharing his manuscript with me. |
20 | |
21 | In “Judaism and the Jews” (1909), Buber writes that “blood is a deep-rooted, nurturing force within the individual; that the deepest layers of our being are determined by blood” (Buber 1995, p. 15). In the 1960s, Buber regretted this language: “Several years after the authorship of these things, evil people distorted the term ‘blood’ that I used. This is why I find it appropriate to announce that wherever I used the language of blood I referred in no way to the racial matter, which in my view is baseless, but to the succession of birth giving within a nation, which is the skeleton of its essence” (Cited from (Ram 2017, p. 270). Appears originally in Hebrew: (Buber 1959, p. 29)). More on this topic, see also: (Biale 2007, pp. 185–86). |
22 | In a letter to Hugo Bergman (February 1918), Buber writes: “We must face the fact that most leading Zionists (and probably also most of those who are led) today are thoroughly unrestrained nationalists (following the European example), imperialists, even mercantilists and idolaters of success. They speak about rebirth and mean enterprise. If we do not succeed to erect an authoritative [Zionist] opposition, the soul of the movement will be corrupted, maybe forever. I for my part am determined to commit myself totally to this cause, even if this should affect my personal plans …” (Buber 1983, p. 38). |
23 | Buber followed Ferdinand Tönnies’ definition, see: (Mendes-Flohr 1989b, pp. 76–82). See also: (Silberstein 1989, p. 33). |
24 | Biemann argues that “though neo-Romantic ideas pervaded much of his earlier thought,” Buber insisted in his speech Herut (1918) that “his renaissance will not be mistaken for romanticism” (Biemann 2006, p. 105). |
25 | Ohana accentuates Buber’s later critique of Nietzsche (Ohana 2018, pp. 147–51). |
26 | For more on Spengler’s mythic historicism in the context of the fin de siècle, see (Bambach 2013, pp. 133–49; Herf [1984] 1986, pp. 49–69). |
27 | The term Irdisch, meaning earthly, refers to the Jews as materialists. Rationality, calculation and profit were identified with this earthly attitude, which contradicted the Volkish love for the land and the authentic relationship to Mother Earth (Mutter-Erde). Moreover, influenced perhaps by neo-marcionism, the Jews were considered an earthly (materialist) force in the world which threatened to destroy the human spirit (Geist). |
28 | Heidegger accuses the Jews of being empty in spirit and uprooted. My essay on the topic discusses Heidegger’s approach in light of the Black Notebooks (Hadad 2017). |
29 | E.g., in Oswald Spengler, The Decline of The West (1923) and Alfred Rosenberg, The Myth of the Twentieth Century (1930). |
30 | Franz Rosenzweig was also an admirer of myth. He adopted enthusiastically Schelling’s program of myth, where philosophy and myth were envisioned to entangle: Philosophy shall become mythic and myth shall become philosophical (Schwarz 1978). Not only with regard to myth but also with regard to mysticism, Buber is considered innovative. Gershom Scholem highlights Buber as the first thinker to recognize that Jewish mysticism was a “[b]asic feature and continuously operating tendency of Judaism” (Scholem 1976, p. 145; Huss 2008, p. 98). For more on the connection between myth and mysticism and their relation to Hasidism, see Buber’s “Die Jüdische Mystik” (Buber [1906] 1916, pp. 5–8). See, in particular, Mendes-Flohr’s essay “Fin-de-siècle Orientalism, the Ostjuden, and the Aesthetics of Jewish Self-Affirmation.” Mendes-Flohr juxtaposes Buber’s interest in myth and Hasidism with Zeitgeist trends, especially neo-Romanticism and the interest in mysticism and the Orient in Germany. Buber himself acknowledges this affinity later in his life (Mendes-Flohr 1984, p. 112; Mendes-Flohr and Gries 1988). |
31 | Thus, Buber writes in “Myth in Judaism” (1913): “One went still further, juxtaposing polytheistic peoples as myth-making, and monotheistic peoples as mythless. The Jews were counted among the latter, the mythless people, and as such were either glorified or held in contempt” (Buber 1995, p. 95). |
32 | Buber contends: “The Jews are a people that has never ceased to produce myth. In ancient times arose the stream of myth-bearing power that flowed—for the time being—into Hasidism” (Buber 2002b, p. xi). |
33 | |
34 | Although rejected officially and neglected by Rabbis and Maskilim, Buber affirmed that myth never ceased to exist in Judaism. See fn.32. |
35 | Admiel Kosman thinks of Myth in Buber as a way to surmount the limitations of language. According to him, myth is a transmission of the “word of the heart” from one generation to the next. Tales engage the reader in an experience which conveys that which cannot otherwise be expressed. Spiritual or religious inter-generational dialogue is conducted through myth (Kosman 2017, p. 216). |
36 | Even though Buber did not apply the term ‘myth’ to his Biblical commentaries, instead using the term ‘saga’ or ‘Aggada’—as suggested by Sufrin—it seems to be a choice which is affected by historical circumstances rather than a thematic distinction. Sufrin claims that “by 1933 in Germany, the term myth had been transformed from its Romantic roots into a tool for National Socialism. Turning to the word saga instead of myth allowed Buber to escape the anti-Semitic connotations that had gathered around the latter term” ((Sufrin 2012, p. 144); see also: (Sufrin 2013, p. 85)). I therefore use the word myth to describe both Biblical stories and Hasidic stories. Buber however, did not entirely neglect the notion of myth, but reused it later in the post-war era. For instance, in his essay “Hasidism and the modern Man” (1956), he accentuates his position against de-mythologizing religion: “I cannot concur with the postulate of the hour—to demythologize religion” (Buber 2002a, p. 92). |
37 | On the identity of the religious and ethics in Buber, see: (Statman and Sagie 1986). |
38 | Hitler claimed that “conscience is a Jewish invention.” Buber mentions it in “People and Leader” (1942) and “Crisis and Truth” (1945). See: (Buber 1984, pp. 62–74, 80–81). |
39 | This idea that stems from Nietzsche’s On the Genealogy of Morality (1887), which describes the Jews’ invention of conscience as part of the “revolt of the slaves” who created the “slave morality” (Christianity) in an attempt to achieve self-empowerment against the Roman Empire. The Jews “conquered” Rome this way. See more in “Nietzsche in the Third Reich” (Aschheim 1992, pp. 232–71). About Nietzsche’s understanding of Judaism, see: (J. Simon 1997). |
40 | Mostly, however, Buber, accepts Plato’s definitions and relationship to myth, and only sharpens his approach against Plato’s. For instance, here: “We are dealing here, as Plato already knew, with truths such as can be communicated adequately to the generality of mankind only in the form of myths. The anthropological exposition shows the domain in which they materialize again and again. Everything conceptual in this connection is merely an aid, a useful bridge between myth and reality” (Buber 1952, p. 66). |
41 | In “Myth in Judaism” (1913), Buber claims that “to the Jew corporeal reality is a revelation of the divine spirit and will. Consequently, all myth is for the Indian sage, as later for the Platonist, a metaphor, whereas for the Jew it is a true account of God’s manifestation on earth. The Jew of antiquity cannot tell a story in any other way than mythically, for to him an event is worth telling only when it has been grasped in its divine significance” (Buber 1995, p. 105). |
42 | See also: (Mali 2012). |
43 | Buber’s Letter to Gandhi (1939) reveals his theopolitical disposition against the Volkish nationalist claim of land ownership (Buber 1983, pp. 111–25). |
44 | The term Eretz ha-Avot (the land of the forefathers), as such, can be found abundantly in modern and Zionist literature. It is, however, not as prevalent in earlier periods; in rabbinic and Midrash literature and in the Middle Ages, the expressions Nakhalat ha-Avot and Yerushat ha-Avot were more in use. The origin of the term lies, however, in the Biblical myth according to which the land of Canaan was promised to the forefathers and their decedents (Deuteronomy 1:8), or when God asked Jacob to return to Eretz Avotekha (Genesis 31:3). I thank Admiel Kosman for illuminations and references. For further reading, see also: (Guttmann 1929). |
45 | Superiority does not originate in the Hebrew Bible. In fact, it appears in other ancient cultures, for instance the Greeks and Romans. Raphael Jospe, in “The Concept of the Chosen People—An interpretation,” explains that while chosenness as a specifically theological notion may well be unique to the Jewish people (and to those Christians who see the Church as supplanting or supplementing the Jews as Verus Israel), there are radical parallels in other cultures in the ancient world. According to Jospe, “The Jews are not the only nation to see themselves as distinctive and special, […] the Greeks took understandable pride, however arrogant from our [post-modern] point of view, in their accomplishments, and their regard for the nations they encountered and conquered as barbaroi was not always unwarranted. The Romans took over from the Greeks much of this sense of historic superiority […].” Jospe also demonstrates that the pagan mind can go much further than claiming divine election; it can regard nations as being of divine descent (Jospe 1994, pp. 128–29). |
46 | For instance, the rejection of modernity and democracy, understanding Christianity as a “sickness” and the striving for a return to a golden age. See: (Young 2006, p. 206). |
47 | Carl Schmitt’s god-like leadership may have been inspired by Nietzsche’s Übermensch (Ohana 2018, pp. 147–51). Buber opposed Carl Schmitt’s attempt to secularize theology and utilize it in service to power-politics. His theopolitics is an objection to Schmitt’s political theology. For more on this, see: (Mendes-Flohr 2008; Brody 2015, 2018; Schmidt 2016; Kaplan 2014; Schaefer 2017; Lesch 2018). I thank Itamar Ben-Ami for alerting me to the last publication. |
48 | John Caputo in his essay “People of God, People of Being” (2000) at the intentional oblivion of the Hebraic in Heidegger’s writing. He claims that “Heidegger has constructed a rival narrative of Being—structurally analogous in all of its main points to the biblical model, that is the narrative of the Jews and their God in the Tanach” (Caputo 2000, p. 90). Caputo concludes his essay, as indicated by Elad Lapidot (Lapidot 2016), with a general critique of Judaism: “Heidegger reproduces the myth of God’s chosen people, of God’s promised land, which is no less a problem for religion and the root of its violence. We need to break the logic that allows the myth to flourish that certain human beings speak the language that being or God would speak, had they vocal chords and lungs and writing instruments, the murderous twin myths of the people of God and of the people of being, myths which license murder in the name of God or in the name of the question of being” (Caputo 2000, p. 91). Heidegger’s Volkism was identified by Caputo with the Hebrew Bible. Other recent examples for this discourse can also be found in the works of Regina Schwartz (Schwartz 1997) and Jan Assmann (J. Assmann [2003] 2010), who view the Hebrew Bible and ancient monotheism as a source of western violence. Both scholars argue that the polytheistic religions are more tolerant and pluralistic worldviews than the monotheist. |
49 | Torat Israel for Buber was anti-Volkish in principle. If, for Nietzsche, “Christianity represented the victory of the antivolkish principle over the nations” and in so doing “penetrated Greek antiquity” and destroyed the Dionysian essence (Aschheim 1992, p. 251)—then Buber saw in Torat Israel the antivolkish principle which should guide the nations, a principle which could overcome (if understood properly) the sheer primitive naturalist tribal connection to soil and blood towards a higher goal of human brotherhood and mutual building of the dialogical kingdom upon earth. |
50 | To learn more about the intimate connection between biblical Myth and Hasidic tales in Buber’s thought, see: (Urban 2004). |
51 | Claire Sufrin explains that, for Buber, God’s pre-Sinai connection to the ancestors (the fathers of the nation: Abraham, Isaak and Jacob) was greater than his connection to the Israelites (Sufrin 2013, p. 88). The covenant itself, according to Buber, is a commitment to conduct dialogue: “We have here not ‘a solemn covenant-ceremony’, but a solemn dialogue” (Buber 1967, p. 123). Sufrin also views dialogue as an essential element in the biblical stories. |
52 | This idea appears in many places in The Prophetic Faith and Kingship of God; I quote one example: “[...] God does not attach decisive importance to ‘religion.’ Other gods are dependent on a house, an altar, sacrificial worship, because without these things they have no existence, their whole nature consisting only of what the creatures give them; whereas “the living God and eternal king” (10, 10; a post-Jeremianic saying, but in his spirit) is not dependent upon any of these things, since He is. He desires no religion, He desires a human people, men living together, the makers of decision vindicating their right to those thirsting for justice, the strong having pity on the weak (7, 5f), men associating with men” (Buber 1960, p. 171). |
53 | See this idea of unification of the religious and moral in Judaism also in Buber’s earlier essay “The Holy Way” (1918) (Buber 1995, pp. 108–48) and in (Statman and Sagie 1986). |
54 | Buber speaks about dialogue with three kinds of entities, two of them non-human: Natural beings (“life with nature”) and spiritual beings (“life with spiritual beings”), see: (Buber 1970, pp. 56–57). For more on the theological and spiritual aspects of dialogue in Buber’s thought, see: (Kosman 2007, 2013). On Hasidic influences in Buber’s I and Thou, see: (Koren 2010). I thank Admiel Kosman for inspiring conversations on this topic. |
55 | |
56 | Buber’s Kingdom of God does not strive to create a state. In Menachem Lorberbaum’s words: “Buber maintains that the pursuit of statehood is the classic political expression of idolatry. He argues that giving up the ‘holy anarchy’ of the Judges for a centralized form of government and replacing the charismatic judge moved by the immediacy of the divine spirit with an institutionalized hereditary monarchy is a forsaking of theocracy—God’s rule—for human power” (Lorberbaum 2001, p. 10). For more on Buber’s objection to statehood, see his correspondence with Hermann Cohen (1916) in (Buber 1984, pp. 147–62). I thank Ronen Pinkas for reminding me of the debate in this context. |
57 | Fichte in his Addresses to the German Nation (1807–1808) “portrayed the Germans as a “chosen people” whose mission was to ennoble mankind” (Stackelberg 1981, p. 5). |
58 | In this regard, Buber is not innovating, but continuing the main traditional interpretations of election as a moral or religious or ethical duty rather than privilege. See: (Almog and Hed 1991). |
59 | Even within Israel, not all are elected; in Israel, says Buber, the majority was always drawn after the golden calf (Buber 1973, pp. 84, 119). |
60 | Buber says that: “The world is God’s field, the peoples His plantation, Israel His first-fruits. Just as the tree offers him, the giver of the land, the first-fruits every year, so Israel must offer itself to Him as the first-fruits of His world harvest” (Buber 1973, p. 8). |
61 | Israel as first born (Buber 2002a, p. 26). |
62 | The Divine Kingdom means a community “out of free will.” If God does not coerce the human, no human or nation for that matter shall coerce each other to become His: This world is “a world which does not want to be God’s,” and God “does not want to compel the world to become His” (Buber 1967, pp. 138–39). |
63 | Buber thought of the folk of Israel as a community of blood (Buber 1995, p. 15) which is not established, however, on the purity of blood. |
64 | See also: “It is Israel that the land has been given to it by God for the sake of Israel’s special task: that of being the ‘beginning of His harvest’. It is its own fault that it did not fulfil this task while it was living in the land. And because of this it has been exiled” (Buber 1973, p. 89). |
65 | That notwithstanding, the mission remains theirs according to Buber: “[N]evertheless, the covenant between God, people and land […] has not come to an end, nor shall it do so” (Buber 1973, pp. 29–30). |
66 | Buber does not say that in his Book On Zion (1944) (Buber 1973), but it is clear from his many protests against possession of the land and the need to cooperate with the Arabs for a peaceful life on the land (e.g., “The Treason” (Buber 1984, pp. 327–29), “Our Pseudo-Samsons” (1939) (Buber 1983, pp. 130–33), “Concerning our Politics” (1939) (Buber 1983, pp. 137–41). |
67 | In his essay “People and Leader” (1942), Buber recapitulates the essence of true myth in the following words: “[Myth is] the corporeal description of a non-corporeal secret, which is not pronounceable, and the human that created it and believes in it becomes a strange creature. Indeed, it articulates the emotions of the masses, their tendencies and beliefs, but those who walk ahead spiritually acknowledge it as a most valuable daydream” (Buber 1984, p. 63; my translation). |
68 | In his essay, Tishby (1967) provides an overview of the emergence of Hasidism as perceived by its main theoretician at the time. Against an earlier trend in the study of Hasidism which viewed Hasidim as a branch of Sabbateanism itself, Tishby indicates that all main scholars of the time, e.g., Dinur and Dubnow, and both Buber and Scholem, abandoned this view and held a different view according to which Hasidism emerged as an attempt to repair the damages of Sabbateanism and Frankism. Hasidism, according to them, was a reaction to Sabbateanism and its deterioration. All agreed that Hasidism performed a profound change in the way messianism was interpreted in Sabbateanism. However, whereas Gershom Scholem held the view that Hasidim neutralized messianism, Ben-Zion Dinur held the opinion that Hasidism was established from the intention to purify messianism from the husks of Sabbateanism. Dinur therefore uses the Kabbalistic term ‘purification’ to explain the Hasidic “activism” and its emergence in history as phenomena of Tikun. Buber’s myth-activism reminds me in this respect of Dinur’s interpretation. |
69 | In his essay “Hebrew Humanism” (1941), Buber repeats this idea: “What [the Bible has] to tell us, and what no other voice in the world can teach us with such simple power, is that there is truth and there are lies and that human life cannot persist or have meaning save in the decision in behalf of truth and against lies; that there is right and wrong, and that the salvation of man depends on choosing what is right and rejecting what is wrong (Cited in (Sufrin 2013, p. 98). Appears in (Buber 1997, p. 246); my emphasis). |
70 | Moshe Halamish explains the idea of purification with respect to one’s own religious and spiritual work: “In the teaching of R. Isaac Luria, every individual is a participant in the active process of the world’s tikkun by the very act of doing good. This process is called “clarifying the sparks” (berur ha’ala’at or “raising the sparks”). The completion of the process takes place with the arrival of redemption itself” (Halamish 1999, p. 182). |
71 | In his essay “Understanding the National Idea” (1949), Buber argues that the real national task is first and foremost internal and does not involve other nations. It is an educational and cultural task, where the good national elements should be sorted out from bad elements. Cultural nationalism, in Buber’s eyes, is the answer to the national “insanity” that regards every national fruition as noble and great: “The true national task is internal, cultural, educational; it is the need to weed the folk’s herb garden, and nurture the good […] [but] the ‘national insanity,’ growing increasingly, does not know to make distinctions between good and bad herbs; nationalism has no criteria to make such a distinction, because every national herb is in its eyes, precisely because of its nationality, a noble herb” (Buber 1984, pp. 206–7; my translation). |
72 | See, for instance, what Buber says in “Isaiah and Plato”: “Plato believed that his soul was perfect. Isaiah did not. Isaiah regarded and acknowledged himself as unclean” (Buber 1963, p. 235). The servant of God (Eved ha-Shem) is under a constant process of distinction and purification of his soul, and does not presume like Plato that his soul has become perfect. Judaism in Buber’s understanding abolishes any assumption of human perfection, or any pure types of goodness (or evil), and focuses on the process of constant improvement by way of Tikun, which has no static end. |
73 | Buber claims that in Judaism the bad has no essence of its own; “what we call evil is no essence, but a lack. It is ‘God’s exile,’ the lowest rung of the good, the throne of the good. It is—in the language of the old Kabbala—the ‘shell’ that surrounds and disguises the essence of things” (Buber 1956, p. 13; Buber [1906] 1916, pp. 15–16). |
74 | On Buber and Rosenzweig’s activism against Gnosis, see: (Mendes-Flohr 1991, pp. 207–36). On Franz Rosenzweig’s early Marcionism, see: (Pollock 2014). See also: Sufrin on Buber’s and Scholem’s respective understanding of Gnosticism (Sufrin 2012, p. 136). On Buber’s understanding of Gnosis, see: (Feller 2013). More generally on Gnosis and Zionism, see: (Hotam 2007) |
75 | Nota bene that Buber shows ambivalence toward Kabbalah; sometimes he thinks of it as Gnostic, and celebrates Hasidism as a “protest against Kabbalah” (Buber 1966, p. 178), and other times, like in this example, he refers to it as aligning with Hasidism’s anti-dualist worldview. For more on Buber’s antagonistic relationship to Kabbalah, see: (Shonkoff 2018, pp. 9–10). |
76 | Buber was not a radical pacifist; he rejected Gandhi’s demand for satayagrah—non-violent resistance in the face of death—and prefers self-defense in facing violence and evil (Buber 1983, pp. 111–25). Self-defense in the face of evil differs, radically, from any idea of proactive annihilation. |
77 | Buber makes the connection between this Hasidic idea and the psychological Freudian idea of sublimation of the libido (Buber 1966, p. 83). |
© 2019 by the author. Licensee MDPI, Basel, Switzerland. This article is an open access article distributed under the terms and conditions of the Creative Commons Attribution (CC BY) license (http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/).
Share and Cite
Hadad, Y. Hasidic Myth-Activism: Martin Buber’s Theopolitical Revision of Volkish Nationalism. Religions 2019, 10, 96. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel10020096
Hadad Y. Hasidic Myth-Activism: Martin Buber’s Theopolitical Revision of Volkish Nationalism. Religions. 2019; 10(2):96. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel10020096
Chicago/Turabian StyleHadad, Yemima. 2019. "Hasidic Myth-Activism: Martin Buber’s Theopolitical Revision of Volkish Nationalism" Religions 10, no. 2: 96. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel10020096
APA StyleHadad, Y. (2019). Hasidic Myth-Activism: Martin Buber’s Theopolitical Revision of Volkish Nationalism. Religions, 10(2), 96. https://doi.org/10.3390/rel10020096