The Ubiquity of Humanity and Textuality in Human Experience
Abstract
:1. Introduction: How to Make Humanities Relevant
2. Ubiquitous Humanity
2.1. The Ubiquity of Humanity: Asking a Question
2.2. The Notion of Humanity
2.3. Intervening Non-Humanity
3. Ubiquitous Textuality
3.1. Text and Context
3.2. Non-Verbal Language
3.3. Film Language
4. Textuality of Humanities
4.1. Denotation of Classic Humanity
4.2. Humanity and Humanities
4.3. Divisional Humanities and Post-Divisional Humanities
5. Human Solidarity
5.1. Humanity and Anthropology
5.2. Liberalism vs. Communalism
5.3. Human Bonding and the Division of Labor
6. Conclusions: Ubiquities and Humanities
Acknowledgments
Conflicts of Interest
References
- Jürgen Habermas. The Philosophical Discourse of Modernity. Cambridge: MIT Press, 1987. [Google Scholar]
- Daihyun Chung. “Reference Naturalized in Yinyang Ontology.” Cheolhak 120 (2014): 27–52. [Google Scholar]
- George Church, and Ed Regis. Regenesis: How Synthetic Biology Will Reinvent Nature and Ourselves. New York: Basic Books, 2012. [Google Scholar]
- Henry Hiz. “Introduction.” In Questions. Edited by Henry Hiz. Dordrecht: Reidel, 1978. [Google Scholar]
- Charles H. Kahn. “Questions and Categories.” In Questions. Edited by Henry Hiz. Dordrecht: Reidel, 1978. [Google Scholar]
- Daihyun Chung. This Spoken Thus: Pluralistic Realism. Seoul: Sechang, 2013. [Google Scholar]
- “Ae-Ryung Kim’s discussions.” Available online: http://ioh.snu.ac.kr/bbs/board.php?bo_table=symposium&wr_id=35&auto_login=1 javascript:file_download('./download.php? (accessed on 1 February 2015).
- Ynhui Park. “The Self-Deconstructive Process of Art as a Form of Reconstruction of the World.” In The Crisis of Civilization and Asian Response. Seoul: Seoul National University Press, 2012. [Google Scholar]
- Arne Naess. Ecology, Community and Lifestyle: Outline of an Ecoophy. Translated by David Rothenberg. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1989. [Google Scholar]
- Willard van Orman Quine. Word and Object. Cambridge: MIT Press, 1960. [Google Scholar]
- Daniel Kahneman. Thinking, Fast and Slow. London: Allen Lane, 2011. [Google Scholar]
- Saul A. Kripke. Wittgenstein on Rules and Private Language. Oxford: Blackwell, 1982. [Google Scholar]
- Robert Stalnaker. “On the Representation of Context.” In Context and Content. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1999. [Google Scholar]
- Daihyun Chung. Philosophy of Fitting: Toward a Theory of Truth and Meaning. Seoul: Cheolhakgwa Hyeonsilsa, 1997. [Google Scholar]
- Daihyun Chung. “Lingualism in Graham’s Night Journey.” The Korean Journal of Dance Studies 27 (2009): 95–115. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Nelson Goodman. Languages of Art: An Approach to a Theory of Symbols. Indianapolis: Hackett, 1976. [Google Scholar]
- Joseph Margolis. “Dance as Language.” In What is Dance? Edited by Roger Copeland and Marshall Cohen. New York: Oxford UP, 1983, pp. 376–89. [Google Scholar]
- Richard Allen. “Looking at Motion Pictures.” In Film Theory and Philosophy. Edited by Richard Allen and Murray Smith. Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1997, pp. 76–94. [Google Scholar]
- Malcolm Turvey. “Seeing Theory.” In Film Theory and Philosophy. Edited by Richard Allen and Murray Smith. Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1997, pp. 431–57. [Google Scholar]
- Ludwig Wittgenstein. Philosophical Investigations. New York: Macmillan, 1953. [Google Scholar]
- “Sung Yong Kang’s discussions.” Available online: http://ioh.snu.ac.kr/bbs/board.php?bo_table=symposium&wr_id=35&auto_login=1javascript: file_download (accessed on 1 February 2015).
- “Workshop on Digital Culture, Korea Culture Research Institute, Ewha Womans University, Seoul, South Korea.” 1999. Available online: www.ewha.ac.kr/mbs/ewhaen/subview.jsp?id=ewhaen _040301010700 (accessed on 15 June 2015).
- Jongkwan Lee. Cyberculture and Temptation of Art. Seoul: Moonye, 2003. [Google Scholar]
- Kihyeon Kim. Contemporary Epistemology. Seoul: Minumsa, 2011. [Google Scholar]
- Insuk Ko. “Feyerabend’s critique of Popperian Rationality of Science: Meaning of the Theory Proliferation.” Beomhancheolhak 28 (2003): 5–30. [Google Scholar]
- “The notion of classic.” Available online: https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Western_canon (accessed on 15 June 2015).
- Harold Bloom. The Western Canon: The Books and School of the Ages. New York: Riverhead Books, 1995. [Google Scholar]
- John R. Searle. “The Storm over the University.” In The New York Review of Books. New York: The New York Times, 1990. [Google Scholar]
- Daihyun Chung, Ynhui Park, Jong-Ho Yoo, Chiesou Kim, Joo Youn Kim, DukAe Chung, Gyu Sung Lee, and Seong-Man Choi. Humanity to Be Expressed. Seoul: Thinking Tree, 2000. [Google Scholar]
- Daihyun Chung. “Interconnected Realizations of Self and of All Others.” Beomhancheolhak 36 (2005): 97–125. [Google Scholar]
- Daihyun Chung. “Integrationality(誠): From dualism to yinyang.” Cheolhangnonjip 9 (2005): 73–88. [Google Scholar]
- John Stuart Mill. Collected Works of John Stuart Mill. Toronto: University of Toronto Press, 1963, vol. 8, pp. 844–48. [Google Scholar]
- Charles Taylor. Philosophy and the Human Sciences: Philosophical Papers 2. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1985, p. 309. [Google Scholar]
- Terence Ball, Richard Dagger, and Daniel I. O’Neill. Political Ideologies and the Democratic Ideal. North York: Pearson Education Canada, 2014, pp. 47–51. [Google Scholar]
- Martin Luther. “Commentary on Galatians.” In Concordia Theological Monthly. Fort Wayne: Concordia Theological Seminary, 1955, p. 801. [Google Scholar]
- Gerald F. Gaus. “Property, Rights, and Freedom.” Social Philosophy and Policy 11 (1994): 209–40. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- John Rawls. A Theory of Justice. Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1993, p. 56. [Google Scholar]
- Richard Rorty. Objectivity. Relativism, and Truth: Philosophical Papers. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1991, vol. 1. [Google Scholar]
- Michael Walzer. Spheres of Justice: A Defense of Pluralism and Equality. New York: Basic Books, 1983. [Google Scholar]
- Young Jin Choi. “Issues on Modernization of Confucianism.” In Issues on Korean Philosophy. Seoul: Cheolhakgwa Hyeonsilsa, 2000, pp. 121–49. [Google Scholar]
- 1The idea that human language is a mirror of humanity is nothing new. When Aristotle said that humans are rational, Chomsky that language is innate, and Wittgenstein that humans play a language game, one may see the idea behind their remarks. What I try to do here with the idea is to show through an analysis of the notion of question that humans are themselves active agents who connect language and humanity; that humans, language, and humans are necessarily integrated with each other; and that the presence of one indicates the presence of the other two.
- 2There are various discussions about the notion of a question. For example, G. Stahl proposed that the meaning of a question is a set of correct answers ([4], pp. ix–xvii), C. H. Kahn was leaning toward a view that questions are attempts to categorize human experiences ([5], pp. 227–78). But I tried here to go further to relate the notion of question both to the notions of language and humanity.
- 3Sangkyu Shin and Ae-Ryung Kim [7] have raised objections to my attempt to connect the ubiquitous humanity thesis to the notion of language use. Kim suggests that the connection may depend on a choice of values stemming from a certain usage of language, and Shin observes that the connection would be circular unless the two theses of ubiquitous humanity and language use are independently defended. The two criticisms are plausible. However, human beings cannot escape from the languages into which they are placed; they are bound to construct the nature of their own relationships through linguistic communication. Therefore, their apparent choice of values and the logic of integration between humanity and language are interwoven in the natural history of their evolution.
- 4The expression “wholesome” can be understood under the concept of integration which has been developed by the ideas like fitting and integration given in footnotes 4 and 10. For the time being, one sense of the term would be sufficient when the term applies to objects of art. The notion of an object of art is itself in need of explanation. One suitable definition, which comes from Yunhui Park ([8], pp. 249–59) is that of “a possible unique world”. On this characterization, “possible” designates a modality where there is a property of freer space. “Unique” refers to a property of construction which is creative, autonomous, and independent. And “world” indicates that an art object is not an independent subject but part of a system of objects that require interpretation.
- 5In the present context of the discussion of humanity I limited myself to the boundary of humanity where natural languages are accessible. One may extend the discussion to the wider context where humanity may be taken to be seen as an ecological property ([9], pp. 163–82).
- 6Quine’s notion of semantic ascent is used here to shed light on the concept of humanity ([10], pp. 270–76). Ontologically factual statements like “there are unicorns in Tasmania” are interpreted as statements such as “there are biological species of which the predicate ‘being a unicorn’ is true.” A story of unclear objects is turned into a story of clear vocabularies. Quine goes further to say that existence is the value of a bound variable. His goal was to explain the unclear notion of existence in terms of the clear grammar of a language. This notion of semantic ascent is useful in the context of humanity. For humanity can be grasped as a power to achieve the value of freedom out of a given states of affairs. Humans are exposed to intrusion and the dominion of non-humanity. Non-humanity emerges not only in the context of violence, oppression, and the objectification of persons, but also in the background deterioration of the global environment. Semantic ascent in the context of this non-humanity means an effort to turn the conditions of objectified human lives into the conditions of a better order of the grammar of a language. This effort includes among other descriptions of those negative human conditions, clarifications of the shared objectives of a community, critical evaluations of the present negative predicaments, comparisons among alternative directions, dialogues towards a consensus. This effort involves linguistic deliberations and communal communication, elevating a perspective from one dimensional physical surroundings to a higher multi-dimensional conceptual levels. Such semantic ascent attempts to strengthen human solidarity or to extend our understanding of the worlds around us. The application of semantic ascent to the context of humanity may look non-Quinean to some, but it is useful for the purposes of this article.
- 7As for notions like silence and solitude, I will make a distinction between the positive ones and the negative ones. The positive ones are those which enhance human potentialities, being derived from one’s own choice and initiation, whereas the negative ones are those which hinder human possibilities, coming from other than one’s own freedom.
- 8The reason why one turns to theories of language use rather than to theories of reference should be obvious. For I happen to believe that there is no fact of the matter on which the meaning of an expression can depend on, as Kripke ([12], pp. 1–54) has shown.
- 9There are various notions of context, many of which are slippery. The concept of context my argument relies on is a modal notion which was constructed by R. C. Stalnaker ([13], pp. 96–114), where (i) contexts are all the situations which speakers recognize during their discourses; (ii) assertions are a kind of proposals to change contexts through exchange of information of situations; and (iii) if a world is all the situations there are then if a possible world wi were materialized then wi is all the situations given to speakers in that world.
- 10Another example that connects text and context is found in the claim that the meaning of an expression is the way in which it is used. The idea of “the way in which an expression is used” can be grasped by the notion of fitting ([14], pp. 420–39). The conception of fitting, like those of other value terms, can be thought of as having temporal stages of evolution in the following 6 steps: (i) All animals have likes and dislikes. They like what is useful for their survival and dislike what is not; (ii) Animals might not have the power of recognition in the initial stages of their evolution. It could be that dogs could recognize their masters only after a long process of cognitive development. A dog’s recognition may be explained by its capacity to fittingly adjust to contexts rather than a simple theory of truth semantics. In the beginning, dogs might not be able to discriminate their masters from others. But as they meet their masters repeatedly they come to recognize their masters. Acquaintance might be related with qualities which are useful for their survival. It can be said that dogs have come to discriminate what is fitting from what is not; (iii) Human beings construct habits of fitting by employing the criterion of fitting which they have learnt through acquaintance with their environments, habits fitting for their survival. Habits are not only convenient but also efficient, not only economically but also mechanically; (iv) When habits are constructed, the relation of fitting for the habits becomes a value. Habits supervene on the structure of likes and dislikes, and typify the structure; (v) When habits are shared by a sufficient number of people, a community arises out of the shared values. Some human beings build a community as they are gregarious according to their shared values of fitting; (vi) As the form of life in this community includes a communal effort to communicate with each other, means for the communication obtains some communal meaning. The notion of fitting provides a basis for the hypothesis that texts are ubiquitous, that text and context are continuous, not fundamentally separable.
- 11The notion of gestures as languages may be generalized to the notion of states of affairs as languages ([2], pp. 14–15). States of affairs are informative. For example, consider the fact that a magnetic stick attracts iron filings. Physicalism would hold that the magnetic stick and the iron filings have merely passive properties whereas dispositionalism would assert that they have active powers; they interact with each other to manifest the result of their permeabilities. The properties of the magnetic stick and iron filings and the powers that they have are one and the same; they are organic, integrational, and informative. If information is lingual, then so too are states of affairs.
- 12J. Margolis ([17], pp. 376–89) is critical of S. Langer who says that dance is a language. However, Margolis’s arguments are not persuasive ([15], pp. 95–99). For he requires that arts are a language only if arts consist of a convention of rules and there is a symmetry between the presentational symbolism of arts and emotional symbolism of arts, and he thinks that Langer fails to provide the necessary condition, but his notion of arts language is too representational to accommodate.
- 13One may relate a filmic seeing with Wittgenstein’s notion of aspectual seeing ([20], pp. 193–214). When we look at a particular person in a room, all of us can see propositionally that the person is a man, whereas many of us can see aspectually that the person is kind or that the person is not kind. Aspects of an object are neither physical, nor representational.
- 14Sung Yong Kang [21] worries that this sort of language expansion program may hinder language quantification and, furthermore, that it may require that we classify all non-truth functional languages as other than normal or ordinary. This observation would raise a serious objection if one were to hold a truth-conditional semantics. However, the fitting semantics that I endorse grants meanings not only to verbal expressions but also non-verbal expressions.
- 15These are some of the statements Lev Manovich delivered in his lectures in Seoul [22].
- 16One may pay attention to one particular characteristic of my notion of denotation of classic humanity, that is, that my notion is pluralistic. But the notion of classic doesn’t have to be in conflict with the notion of canon [26]. Teachers or institutions may come to favor a particular list of books or art works, depending on their choice of values or objectives, where consistency rules, as they were discussed by Bloom [27] and Searle [28]). Notions of classic and canon play at a different level, with classic working across various cultural traditions at a meta-level and with canon pointing to a particular direction at an object-level.
- 17Ae-Ryung Kim [7] notes that humanity expressed through verbal texts may have a grammar that is different from the grammar of humanity conveyed through non-verbal texts. This is an important reminder. As literature, history, and philosophy have different grammars for revealing humanity in their own proper disciplines, it should be accepted that texts may contain different grammars according to whether the texts are verbal or not. This issue needs further consideration.
- 18The distinction between divisional and post-divisional humanities is relative to the ways the institutions of colleges of humanities are operated. The distinction is arbitrary and needs to be adjusted appropriately to the situation where various needs of institutions may arise. We may recognize one general division of labor where traditional humanities are engaged in verbal texts and contemporary humanities in non-verbal texts. Institutions called “college” and “center” may be allowed to have separate roles to play in this division of labor.
- 19The analysis of the proposition which is expressed by the Chinese sentence 成己成物 can be summed up as follows. This anthropology is based on the idea of integration (誠) of The Doctrine of the Mean. The conception of integration consists of the following five propositions ([30,31]): (i) The integration of a thing is the property of the thing to realize the principles of the thing that are connected with the principles of all others; (ii) “Mind” denotes the power of all things to process information; (iii) Integration is the power of minds, not only of human beings, but also of all other things; (iv) If evolution reflects the history of the development of the present species then history shows the evolution of the intellects of those species and the justice of their forms of life; (v) The integration of a thing is a power to realize itself in the best possible way in a given situation.
- 20Ae-Ryung Kim [7] claims that “the integrational anthropology that realizations of oneself and of all others are one and the same may be interpreted variously depending on a choice of a topographic map of anthropologies.” What Kim means by this is that the theme of power, whether political or not, plays an important role in this context. Of course, the category of power needs to be analyzed in terms of concrete human experiences, but it is the priorities that need to be emphasized here. Human solidarity can be examined in two distinct senses. The relation of human-bonding is the primary sense in which human beings are never to be treated as mere means, whereas the division of labor provides a second sense in which it is practically difficult to treat persons as ends in themselves. This is discussed in more detail in Section 5.3.
- 21The relation between Mill’s liberalism and Luther’s reformation theology can be seen in the following description: “Quite unintentionally, then, the Protestant reformers prepared the way for liberalism. By teaching that salvation comes through faith alone, Luther and the other reformers encouraged people to value individual conscience more than the preservation of unity and orthodoxy. Moving from individual conscience to individual liberty was still a radical step for the time, but it was a step that the early liberals took” ([34], pp. 51, 47–50).
- 22Sung Yong Kang [21] observed that it would be easy to accept the idea that the relation of the human bond is primary, although it would be difficult to institutionalize it. Of course, an individual may look powerless, but through communication individuals can realize the value of their collective intentionality. Studies of appellations in English and French may help in this regard, since acquaintances call each other by their first names, especially between parents and children, and between teachers and students.
© 2015 by the author; licensee MDPI, Basel, Switzerland. This article is an open access article distributed under the terms and conditions of the Creative Commons Attribution license (http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/).
Share and Cite
Chung, D. The Ubiquity of Humanity and Textuality in Human Experience. Humanities 2015, 4, 885-904. https://doi.org/10.3390/h4040885
Chung D. The Ubiquity of Humanity and Textuality in Human Experience. Humanities. 2015; 4(4):885-904. https://doi.org/10.3390/h4040885
Chicago/Turabian StyleChung, Daihyun. 2015. "The Ubiquity of Humanity and Textuality in Human Experience" Humanities 4, no. 4: 885-904. https://doi.org/10.3390/h4040885
APA StyleChung, D. (2015). The Ubiquity of Humanity and Textuality in Human Experience. Humanities, 4(4), 885-904. https://doi.org/10.3390/h4040885