“Without an Analytical Divorce from the Total Environment”: Advancing a Philosophy of the Humanities by Reading Snow and Whitehead Diffractively
Abstract
:1. Introduction
In this book, I have tried to establish a sort of relay between [Alfred North Whitehead and Gilles Deleuze], so that each of them helps to resolve difficulties in the work of the other. […] I am less concerned with reconstructing Whitehead’s thought precisely than in delineating the outlines of the encounter between Whitehead and Deleuze, an encounter that changes our apprehension of both of them.([5], p. xiv, p. 27, footnote 9; emphasis added)
2. Reading Snow through Whitehead
Literary intellectuals at one pole—at the other scientists, and as the most representative, the physical scientists. Between the two a gulf of mutual incomprehension—sometimes (particularly among the young) hostility and dislike, but most of all lack of understanding. They have a curious distorted image of each other. Their attitudes are so different that, even on the level of emotion, they can’t find much common ground.([14], p. 15)
Another great fact confronting the modern world is the discovery or the method of training professionals, who specialise in particular regions of thought and thereby progressively add to the sum of knowledge within their respective limitations of subject. […] This situation has its dangers. It produces minds in a groove. But there is no groove of abstractions which is adequate for the comprehension of human life.([16], pp. 196–97)
I presume that the value to which the aesthetic appreciation of scientific theories refers does not reside in the theories themselves but rather is projected into theories by individual scientists, scientific communities, and observers of science. This amounts to the claim, which I think is very plausible, that we cannot fully describe a scientific theory’s aesthetic value without referring to the effect of properties of that theory on scientists or other observers.([26], p. 31)
They still like to pretend that the traditional culture is the whole of “culture”, as though the natural order didn’t exist. As though the exploration of the natural order was of no interest either in its own value or its consequences. As though the scientific edifice of the physical world was not, in its intellectual depth, complexity and articulation, the most beautiful and wonderful collective work of the mind of man. Yet most non-scientists have no conception of that edifice at all.([14], p. 21)
3. From a Natural Philosophy…
Unless we produce the all-embracing relations, we are faced with a bifurcated nature; namely, warmth and redness on one side, and molecules, electrons and ether on the other side. Then the two factors are explained as being respectively the cause and the mind’s reaction to the cause.([28], p. 32)
[n]ature is […] neither knowable—definable, for instance, as a system of relations between entities—nor unknowable, the famous “mute reality” upon which we project human, linguistic, or social categories. […] Nature is that about which relevant knowledge may be produced. If we pay due attention to it, we can learn, discern relations, and multiply entities and ratios.([22], p. 106)
Where scientific materialism postulates localized entities as the ultimate reference for all explanation, the philosophy of the organism [which is how she refers to Whitehead’s work in this quotation] will ask that the concepts to be constructed exhibit the way nature “explains itself”.([22], p. 144)
4. …through the Study of Beauty…
The problem confronted by such a poem is not that of understanding, of explanation or of establishing the rational relation among the logical subjects—wheelbarrow, rainwater, and white chickens. Rather, the problem is that of sheer knowledge, of how to accede linguistically to the aesthetic value in the sheer relationality and facticity before one’s eyes.
Clear and distinct human sense perception […] is one sort of prehension. A new entity comes into being by prehending other entities; every event is the prehension of other events. All this applies […] not only to the encounter between subject and object, but also to encounters between one object and another, as well as to what is commonly called the “identity” of the individual subject.([5], p. 29)
[…] a judgment of taste [that] involves an uncoerced response, on the part of the subject, to the object that is being judged beautiful. Aesthetic judgment is a kind of recognition: it’s an appreciation of how the object “adapts itself to the way we apprehend it”, even though, at the same time, it remains indifferent to us.([5], p. 2; emphasis in original)
5. …to Non-Reductive Naturalism in the Humanities
[n]ature itself is dynamized, historical, and subject to dramatic change. Sexual difference remains the most creative and powerful means by which this transformation is brought about. It is the means by which the natural cultivates culture, rather than culture cultivating nature.([52], p. 168)
Homosexuality, like racial diversity or difference, […] is one of the many excesses that sexual selection introduces to life, like music, art, and language, excesses that make life more enjoyable, more intense, more noticeable and pleasurable than it would otherwise be.([52], p. 131)
[…] the sense of beauty obviously depends on the nature of the mind, irrespective of any real quality in the admired object; and […] the idea of what is beautiful, [is] not innate or unalterable. […] If beautiful objects had been created solely for man’s gratification, it ought to be shown that before man appeared, there was less beauty on the face of the earth than since he came on stage.(quoted in: [57], p. 51)
6. Conclusions
Acknowledgments
Conflicts of Interest
References and Notes
- Michel Foucault. The Order of Things: An Archaeology of Human Sciences. New York: Vintage Books, 1994, Originally published in 1966. [Google Scholar]
- Wilhelm Dilthey. Introduction to the Human Sciences. Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1989, Originally published in 1883. [Google Scholar]
- Karen Barad. “Meeting the Universe Halfway: Quantum Physics and the Entanglement of Matter and Meaning.” Durham and London: Duke University Press, 2007. [Google Scholar]
- Donna Haraway. “Modest_Witness@Second_Millennium. FemaleMan©_Meets_OncoMouse™: Feminism and Technoscience.” London and New York: Routledge, 1997. [Google Scholar]
- Steven Shaviro. Without Criteria: Kant, Whitehead, Deleuze, and Aesthetics. Cambridge and London: The MIT Press, 2009. [Google Scholar]
- Jacques Derrida. Of Grammatology. Translated by Gayatri Chakravorty Spivak. Baltimore and London: The Johns Hopkins University Press, 1997, Originally published in 1967/1976. [Google Scholar]
- Karen Barad. “Quantum Entanglements and Hauntological Relations of Inheritance: Dis/continuities, SpaceTime Enfoldings, and Justice-to-Come.” Derrida Today 3 (2010): 240–68. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Karen Barad. “On Touching: The Inhuman That Therefore I Am.” differences: A Journal of Feminist Cultural Studies 23 (2012): 206–23. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Vicki Kirby. Quantum Anthropologies: Life at Large. Durham and London: Duke University Press, 2011. [Google Scholar]
- Astrid Schrader. “Responding to Pfiesteria piscicida (the Fish Killer): Phantomatic Ontologies, Indeterminacy, and Responsibility in Toxic Microbiology.” Social Studies of Science 40 (2010): 275–306. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
- Penelope Deutscher. How to Read Derrida. London: Granta Books, 2005. [Google Scholar]
- Iris van der Tuin. “Diffraction as a Methodology for Feminist Onto-Epistemology: On Encountering Chantal Chawaf and Posthuman Interpellation.” Parallax. forthcoming.
- Vicki Kirby. “Deconstruction.” In The Routledge Companion to Literature and Science. Edited by Bruce Clarke and Manuela Rossini. New York: Routledge, 2011, pp. 287–97. [Google Scholar]
- C.P. Snow. “The Two Cultures and the Scientific Revolution.” In Public Affairs. New York: Charles Scribner’s Sons, 1971, pp. 13–46, Originally published in 1959. [Google Scholar]
- C.P. Snow. “The Two Cultures: A Second Look.” In Public Affairs. New York: Charles Scribner’s Sons, 1971, pp. 47–79, Originally published in 1963. [Google Scholar]
- Alfred North Whitehead. Science and the Modern World. New York: Free Press, 1997, Originally published in 1925. [Google Scholar]
- Henri Bergson. Laughter: An Essay on the Meaning of the Comic. Translated by Cloudesely Brereton, and Fred Rothwell. Rockville: Arc Manor, 2008, Originally published in 1900. [Google Scholar]
- Nobelprize.org. “The Nobel Prize in Physics 1957.” Available online: http://www.nobelprize.org/nobel_prizes/physics/laureates/1957/ (accessed on 13 April 2014).
- Henri Bergson. Creative Evolution. Translated by Arthur Mitchell. Mineola: Dover Publications, 1998, Originally published in 1907. [Google Scholar]
- Henri Bergson. The Creative Mind: An Introduction to Metaphysics. Translated by Mabelle L. Andison. Mineola: Dover Publications, 2007, Originally published in 1934. [Google Scholar]
- Keith Robinson, ed. Deleuze, Whitehead, Bergson: Rhizomatic Connections. London: Palgrave Macmillan, 2009.
- Isabelle Stengers. Thinking with Whitehead: A Free and Wild Creation of Concepts. Cambridge and London: Harvard University Press, 2011, Originally published in 2002. [Google Scholar]
- Maura C. Flannery. “Teaching about the Aesthetics of Biology: A Case Study on Rhythm.” Interchange 24 (1993): 5–18. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Christopher Shea. “Is Scientific Truth Always Beautiful? ” Available online: http://chronicle.com/article/When-Beauty-Is-Not-Truth/136803/?cid=at&utm_source=at&utm_medium=en (accessed on 13 April 2014).
- Steven Shapin. Never Pure: Historical Studies of Science as if It Was Produced by People with Bodies, Situated in Time, Space, Culture, and Society, and Struggling for Credibility and Authority. Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press, 2010. [Google Scholar]
- James W. McAllister. Beauty & Revolution in Science. Ithaca and London: Cornell University Press, 1996. [Google Scholar]
- Félix Guattari. The Three Ecologies. Translated by Ian Pindar, and Paul Sutton. London and New York: Continuum, 2008, Originally published in 1989. [Google Scholar]
- Alfred North Whitehead. “Theories of the Bifurcation of Nature.” In The Concept of Nature: The Tarner Lectures Delivered in Trinity College November 1919. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1920, pp. 26–48. [Google Scholar]
- Donna Haraway. The Companion Species Manifesto: Dogs, People, and Significant Otherness. Chicago: Prickly Paradigm Press, 2003. [Google Scholar]
- Karen Barad. “Re(con)figuring Space, Time, and Matter.” In Feminist Locations: Global and Local, Theory and Practice. Edited by Marianne DeKoven. New Brunswick: Rutgers University Press, 2001, pp. 75–109. [Google Scholar]
- Thomas S. Kuhn. The Structure of Scientific Revolutions. Chicago: The University of Chicago Press, 1996, Originally published in 1962/1969. [Google Scholar]
- Gilbert Simondon. ; Translated by Ninian Mellamphy. University of Western Ontario, 1980. On the Mode of Existence of Technical Objects. Available online: http://dephasage.ocular-witness.com/pdf/SimondonGilbert.OnTheModeOfExistence.pdf (accessed on 13 March 2011). Originally published in 1958.
- Bruno Latour. We Have Never Been Modern. Translated by Catherine Porter. London: Prentice Hall, 1993, Originally published in 1991. [Google Scholar]
- Susanne K. Langer. “Feeling and Form: A Theory of Art developed from Philosophy in a New Key.” London: Routledge & Kegan Paul, 1953. [Google Scholar]
- Renée C. Hoogland. A Violent Embrace: Art and Aesthetics after Representation. Hanover: Dartmouth College Press, 2014. [Google Scholar]
- Félix Ravaisson. Of Habit. Translated by Clare Carlisle, and Mark Sinclair. New York and London: Continuum, 2008, Originally published in 1838. [Google Scholar]
- Henri Bergson. “The Life and Work of Ravaisson.” In The Creative Mind: An Introduction to Metaphysics. Translated by Mabelle L. Andison. Mineola: Dover Publications, 2007, pp. 187–216, Originally published in 1904. [Google Scholar]
- Gilles Deleuze, and Félix Guattari. What is Philosophy? New York: Columbia University Press, 1994, Originally published in 1991. [Google Scholar]
- Gregg Lambert. “How to Create a Territory with the Work of Art? ” In Paper presented at the seminar Materialism without Territory—Art and the Environment, CAAD—Chair for Computer Aided Architectural Design, Zürich, Switzerland, May 2014.
- Bruno Latour. Pandora’s Hope: Essays on the Reality of Science Studies. Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1999. [Google Scholar]
- Bruno Latour. “Reflections on Etienne Souriau’s Les différents modes d’existence.” In The Speculative Turn: Continental Materialism and Realism. Edited by Levi Bryant, Nick Srnicek and Graham Harman. Melbourne: re.press, 2011, pp. 304–33. [Google Scholar]
- William Dean. “Whitehead’s Other Aesthetic.” Process Studies 13 (1983): 104–12. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Gregg Lambert. Who’s Afraid of Deleuze and Guattari? London and New York: Continuum, 2006. [Google Scholar]
- Virginia Woolf. Orlando: A Biography. London: Vintage Books, 2004, Originally published in 1928. [Google Scholar]
- Geoffrey H. Hartmann. “Virginia’s Web.” Chicago Review 14 (1961): 20–32. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Ernst Cassirer. “Form and Technology.” In Ernst Cassirer on Form and Technology: Contemporary Readings. Edited by Aud Sissel Hoel and Ingvild Folkvord. Translated by Wilson McClelland Dunlavey, and John Michael Krois. Basingstoke: Palgrave MacMillan, 2012, pp. 15–53, Originally published in 1930. [Google Scholar]
- Aud Sissel Hoel, and Iris van der Tuin. “The Ontological Force of Technicity: Reading Cassirer and Simondon Diffractively.” Philosophy and Technology 26 (2013): 187–202. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Ernst Cassirer. The Logic of the Cultural Sciences. Translated by S.G. Lofts. New Haven and London: Yale University Press, 2000, Originally published in 1942. [Google Scholar]
- Jacques Derrida. ; Translated by David Wills. “The Animal that Therefore I Am (More to Follow).” Critical Inquiry 28 (2002): 369–418. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Donna Haraway. When Species Meet. Minneapolis: The University of Minnesota Press, 2008. [Google Scholar]
- Gilles Deleuze, and Félix Guattari. A Thousand Plateaus: Capitalism and Schizophrenia. Translated by Brian Massumi. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 1987, Originally published in 1980. [Google Scholar]
- Elizabeth Grosz. Becoming Undone: Darwinian Reflections on Life, Politics, and Art. Durham and London: Duke University Press, 2011. [Google Scholar]
- Jonathan Culler. On Deconstruction: Theory and Criticism after Structuralism, 25th anniversary ed. London and New York: Routledge, 2008, Originally published in 1982. [Google Scholar]
- Sara Barns, and Andrew Patrizio. “Darwin on the Threshold of the Visible: Contemporary Art and Evolution.” In The Art of Evolution: Darwin, Darwinisms and Visual Cultures. Edited by Barbara Larson and Fae Brauer. Dartmouth: University Press of New England, 2009, pp. 288–309. [Google Scholar]
- Samantha Frost. “The Implications of the New Materialisms for Feminist Epistemology.” In Feminist Epistemology and Philosophy of Science: Power in Knowledge. Edited by Heidi E. Grasswick. Dordrecht: Springer, 2011, pp. 69–83. [Google Scholar]
- Brian Martin. “Immaterial Land.” In Carnal Knowledge: Towards a New Materialism Through the Arts. Edited by Estelle Barrett and Barbara Bolt. London: I.B. Tauris, 2013, pp. 185–204. [Google Scholar]
- Phillip Prodger. “Ugly Disagreements: Darwin and Ruskin Discuss Sex and Beauty.” In The Art of Evolution: Darwin, Darwinisms and Visual Cultures. Edited by Barbara Larson and Fae Brauer. Dartmouth: University Press of New England, 2009, pp. 40–58. [Google Scholar]
- Quentin Meillassoux. After Finitude: An Essay on the Necessity of Contingency. Edited by Ray Brassier. New York: Continuum, 2008, Originally published in 2006. [Google Scholar]
- Estelle Barrett, and Barbara Bolt, eds. Carnal Knowledge: Towards a New Materialism through the Arts. London and New York: I.B. Tauris, 2013.
- Bettina Papenburg, and Marta Zarzycka, eds. Carnal Aesthetics: Transgressive Imaginary and Feminist Politics. London and New York: I.B. Tauris, 2013.
- Federica Frabetti. “Rethinking the Digital Humanities in the Context of Originary Technicity.” Culture Machine 12 (2011): 1–22. [Google Scholar]
- Felicity Colman. “Affective Feminicity.” In Paper presented at the 8th European Feminist Research Conference, Budapest, Hungary, May 2012.
- Vera Bühlmann. “The Body of the Cypher (An Atomist View on Computational Entities that are Generic in their Kind).” In Paper presented at the seminar Materialism without Territory—Art and the Environment, CAAD—Chair for Computer Aided Architectural Design, Zürich, Switzerland, May 2014.
- 1Whereas the German term “Geisteswissenschaften” seems to cut across the dichotomy between the sciences and the humanities as it stirs questions about the scientificity of the humanities, Dilthey’s subsequent distinction between “Verstehen” and “Erklären” re-installs the gap and Geisteswissenschaften is, therefore, part and parcel of the nineteenth-century Western birth of the disciplines, notwithstanding the interest Dilthey had in sociology, which weakens the dichotomy in the same stroke [2].
- 2Gregg Lambert has reminded me of the fact that Jacques Derrida ([6], pp. 10, 86) used “de-sedimentation” in Of Grammatology as something like a synonym of “de-construction” (according to which the destruction of a text or oeuvre, or an idea or set of ideas is not a demolition). Although the differences and similarities between diffraction and deconstruction—both in the work of Derrida and as a result of its (flawed) canonization (as a methodology)—are still to be researched, I wish to mention here that the diffractive methodology involves the deliberate or accidental study of at least two texts/corpuses at once (which could possibly lead to a dissimilarity with deconstruction) but that Barad—in a conversation with her colleagues Vicki Kirby and Astrid Schrader—moves to Derrida in her later work [7,8,9,10]. An important first observation with regards to the similarities between deconstruction and diffraction could be that whereas diffraction is explicit about its methodological status (one can purposefully begin a diffractive reading of text A and text B, as suggested by Barad; see e.g., [3], p. 232), its workings are as immanent as deconstruction’s workings (one can also “stumble upon” a diffractive reading, when text B presents itself to the reader while immersed in the reading of text A and as intrinsically connected to—even part and parcel of—the latter text; here “intertextuality” is echoed and a study of the differences and similarities between diffraction and intertextuality is in place). The following summarizing statement by Derrida (quoted in: [11], p. 6) suits diffraction perfectly fine: “Deconstruction is not a method or some tool that you apply to something from the outside […] Deconstruction is something which happens and which happens inside; there is a deconstruction at work within Plato’s texts, for instance”. The quote goes well with diffraction, because as soon as a text is diffracted by another text, it has always/already been affected. My previous work has explained this with the strange temporality of Althusserian interpellation [12]. Kirby has made clear how the strange causality of Derridean différance can be used to the same effect (see [13], p. 292).
- 3Lee and Yang got the Nobel Prize in 1957 for proving the violation of the fundamental and purportedly absolute law of parity conservation. See [18].
- 5See for a recent discussion [24].
- 6Steven Shapin calls this how science is “never pure” [25].
- 7It is with an alluring 1801 quote of Friedrich Wilhelm Joseph von Schelling that Whitehead ends his exposition: In the “Philosophy of Nature” I considered the subject-object called nature in its activity of self-constructing. In order to understand it, we must rise to an intellectual intuition of nature. The empiricist does not rise thereto, and for this reason in all his explanations it is always he himself that proves to be constructing nature. It is no wonder, then, that his construction and that which was to be constructed so seldom coincide. A Natur-philosoph raises nature to independence and makes it construct itself, and he never feels, therefore, the necessity of opposing nature as constructed (i.e., as experience) to real nature, or of correcting the one by means of the other (quoted in: [28], pp. 47–48). Should one decide to construct a genealogy of the contemporary humanities based in natureculture metaphysics, inclusion of Romanticism must therefore be secured.
- 8Whitehead strongly compromises the famous idea about “scientific communities” of Thomas S. Kuhn (see [31])—which is related to Snow’s “cultures”—when he states of minds in a groove that “[t]his criticism of modern life applies throughout, in whatever sense you construe the meaning of a community. It holds if you apply it to a nation, a city, a district, an institution, a family, or even to an individual. There is a development of particular abstractions, and a contraction of concrete appreciation. The whole is lost in one of its aspects” ([16], p. 197). This demonstrates that purely descriptive historical work on paradigm-sharing scientific communities is never enough or always/already partial as in “biased”.
- 9As it happens, Snow states that “technology is the branch of human experience that people can learn with predictable results” ([14], p. 40). Note that this sentence was written around the same time as Gilbert Simondon formulated his ideas about the fundamental unpredictability of technological progress [32]. According to the latter, the potentials of human/non-human, organic/inorganic systems only get to be determined when clicking together.
- 10Somebody who has undertaken such a study is Whitehead’s student Susanne K. Langer. See, e.g., her 1953 book Feeling and Form, which is dedicated to Ernst Cassirer [34]. Later in this article it will become clear that this reference to Cassirer is food to future diffractive readings or we can conclude that Langer’s book itself is a diffractive reading of Whitehead and Cassirer.
- 11Note that Whitehead also shifts the pejorative rendering of habit that we find in the work of Bergson. However, we must not forget that the famous reconfiguration of habit by Félix Ravaisson [36] has been appreciated by Bergson, an appreciation we find in the latter’s lengthy in memoriam of Ravaisson written in 1904 (see [37]).
- 12Lambert calls this gathering-together “the creation of a territory with the work of art” [39].
- 13Étienne Souriau explains that this process is also at work in the studio of the artist. Making a sculpture, the artist does not plan, but rather, encounters his work: “A pile of clay on the sculptor’s base. An undeniable, total, accomplished, thingy [réique] existence. But nothing of the aesthetic being exists. Each hand or thumb pressure, each stroke of the chisel accomplishes the work. Don’t look at the chisel, look at the statue. With each act of the demiurge the statue little by little breaks out of its chains. It moves towards existence—towards the existence that will in the end blossom into an existence that is intense, accomplished, and actual. […] Often there is no warning: up to a certain point the finished work is always a novelty, discovery, or surprise. So that’s what I was looking for! That’s what I was meant to make!” (quoted in: [41], p. 310).
- 14A term coined by Barad [3].
- 15Again, this process is also at work at the poet’s desk. As Virginia Woolf wrote in Orlando: “He was describing, as all young poets are for ever describing, nature, and in order to match the shade of green precisely he looked (and here he showed more audacity than most) at the thing itself, which happened to be a laurel bush growing beneath the window. After that, of course, he could write no more. Green in nature is one thing, green in literature another. Nature and letters seem to have a natural antipathy; bring them together and they tear each other to pieces. The shade of green Orlando now saw spoilt his rhyme and split his metre. Moreover, nature has tricks of her own” ([44], p. 5). It must have been for this reason that Geoffrey H. Hartmann wrote in his article “Virginia’s Web”: “Nature […] is one in which the artist participates” ([45], p. 27).
- 16Note that the insertion of neo-Kantian philosopher Cassirer pertains to another diffraction offered by this article. I will argue elsewhere that just like Cassirer’s philosophy of technology fits process-philosophies of technicity (cf. [47]), his “logic of the cultural sciences” fits the philosophy of the humanities such as it is developed in this article [48]. The important point being that this is in spite of the neo-Kantianism according to which his work is usually classified.
- 18Throughout his book Shaviro is keen on highlighting that he is not on the side of the speculative realists/materialists or object-oriented ontologists, for that matter. For instance, he affirms that “[t]he aesthetic subject does not impose its forms upon an otherwise chaotic outside world. Rather, this subject is itself informed by the world outside, a world that (in the words of Wallace Stevens) ‘fills the being before the mind can think’” ([5], p. 13; emphasis in original). The point here is that the speculative realists/materialists would label this a “correlationist” argument (a label that is negatively evaluated) based on Shaviro’s inclusion of the aesthetic subject. Shaviro explicitly reads Whitehead as a theorist of “subjectivity as embedded in the world. The subject is an irreducible part of the universe, of the way things happen” ([5], p. xii).
- 19Cassirer talks about value and Kant too, but his Kant is a wholly different Kant ([48], p. 104). This demonstrates that a diffractive reading does not entail the smoothing out of important differences or tensions.
© 2014 by the author; licensee MDPI, Basel, Switzerland. This article is an open access article distributed under the terms and conditions of the Creative Commons Attribution license (http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/3.0/).
Share and Cite
Van der Tuin, I. “Without an Analytical Divorce from the Total Environment”: Advancing a Philosophy of the Humanities by Reading Snow and Whitehead Diffractively. Humanities 2014, 3, 244-263. https://doi.org/10.3390/h3020244
Van der Tuin I. “Without an Analytical Divorce from the Total Environment”: Advancing a Philosophy of the Humanities by Reading Snow and Whitehead Diffractively. Humanities. 2014; 3(2):244-263. https://doi.org/10.3390/h3020244
Chicago/Turabian StyleVan der Tuin, Iris. 2014. "“Without an Analytical Divorce from the Total Environment”: Advancing a Philosophy of the Humanities by Reading Snow and Whitehead Diffractively" Humanities 3, no. 2: 244-263. https://doi.org/10.3390/h3020244
APA StyleVan der Tuin, I. (2014). “Without an Analytical Divorce from the Total Environment”: Advancing a Philosophy of the Humanities by Reading Snow and Whitehead Diffractively. Humanities, 3(2), 244-263. https://doi.org/10.3390/h3020244