Drawing the Line: Disability, Genetic Intervention and Bioethics
Abstract
:The true good is in the different, not the same.
1. Introduction
[W]e have entered upon a golden age for biology, medicine, and biotechnology. With the completion of (the DNA sequencing phase of) the Human Genome Project and the emergence of stem cell research, we can look forward to major insights into human development, normal and abnormal, as well as novel and more precisely selected treatments for human disease…In myriad ways, the discoveries of biologists and the inventions of biotechnologists are steadily increasing our power ever more precisely to intervene into the workings of our bodies and minds and to alter them by rational design.
2. Classical and Neo-Eugenics
2.1. Classical Eugenics: How Far Have We Gone?
the science of improving stock, which is by no means confined to questions of judicious mating, but [includes] all influences that tend in however remote a degree to give to the more suitable races or strains of blood a better chance of prevailing speedily over the less suitable than they otherwise would have had.
2.2. Genomic Technology as Neo-Eugenics: How Far Have We Come?
One would hope that reactions to the Holocaust and the advent of the disability rights and independent living movements in the U.S. and around the world would have put an end to the eugenic efforts to eliminate disabled people…Unfortunately, if we examine the rhetoric of some influential modern scientists and ethicists, we can see the emergence of a new eugenics tied to the rapid advances in scientific understanding of the human genome.
Human genetics poses a threat to us because while cures and palliatives are promised, what is actually being offered are genetic tests for characteristics perceived as undesirable…These technologies are, therefore, opening the door to a new eugenics which directly threatens our human rights.
3. Disability, Bioethics and Human Rights: Clash or Cooperate?
- (1)
- The traditional utilitarian medical model of disability;
- (2)
- The pro-disability rights perspective of the social model;
- (3)
- The human rights model of disability, a more recently emerging trend amongst disability rights scholarship.
3.1. The Medical Model and Beneficence
- (1)
- what constitutes ‘harm’;
- (2)
- what constitutes ‘good’;
- (3)
- what are the possible negative social consequences that might come from new biomedical technologies in order to protect groups of individuals from that harm.
couples (or single reproducers) should select the child, of the possible children they could have, who is expected to have the best life, or at least as good a life as the others, based on the relevant, available information.
commodities to be ‘serviced’ and…as an economic burden on society; their defects are emphasised and their worth is judged by their contribution to society. Being objects of charity, they are patronised and, at worst, they are perceived as dehumanised ‘others’.
3.2. The Social Model
3.3. Human Rights and Dignitarianism: A Way Forward
First is the absolutely crucial requirement that a person’s physical integrity is respected…Secondly, human dignity means that every person has the inherent right to be treated as an individual with a personality…Thirdly, human dignity means that a person must be given voice about any issues which affect their lives and must have the ability wherever possible to exercise choice. Finally, inherent dignity of any individual requires that he or she has access to a fair share of the goods of society.
How can we live with dignity in societies that spend millions on genetic research to eradicate disease and impairment, but refuse to meet our needs to live dignified and independent lives? We cannot. We will not. The genetic threat to us is a threat to everyone. The value of life must not be reduced to a matter of genetic inheritance.
4. How Do We Regulate?
4.1. International Law
4.1.1. CRPD
- (1)
- regulating the actual use of gene editing technologies like CRISPR; and
- (2)
- in the aftermath of gene editing becoming more readily used, minimising the negative social consequences for persons with disabilities.
4.1.2. UNESCO Declarations: Is Soft Law Tough Enough?
- (1)
- The Universal Declaration on the Human Genome and Human Rights (‘UDHGHR’);
- (2)
- The Universal Declaration on Bioethics and Human Rights (‘UDBHR’); and
- (3)
- The International Declaration on Human Genetic Data (‘IDHGD’).
The human genome underlies the fundamental unity of all members of the human family, as well as the recognition of their inherent dignity and diversity. In a symbolic sense, it is the heritage of humanity.
No one shall be subjected to discrimination based on genetic characteristics that is intended to infringe or has the effect of infringing human rights, fundamental freedoms and human dignity.
In applying and advancing scientific knowledge, medical practice and associated technologies, direct and indirect benefits to patients, research participants and other affected individuals should be maximised and any possible harm to such individuals should be minimised.
In applying and advancing scientific knowledge, medical practice and associated technologies, human vulnerability should be taken into account. Individuals and groups of special vulnerability should be protected and the personal integrity of such individuals respected.
4.2. State Domestic Law
extend across a continuum that distinguishes between degrees of permissiveness, that is, between legally binding legislation and regulatory and/or professional guidance or research versus clinical applications.
- (1)
- the person alters the genome of a human cell in such a way that the alteration is heritable by descendants of the human whose cell was altered; and
- (2)
- in altering the genome, the person intended the alteration to be heritable by descendants of the human whose cell was altered (emphasis added).
5. How Should We Regulate?
5.1. Why a Human-Rights Based Regulatory Framework?
- (1)
- a complete international ban;
- (2)
- a temporary moratorium on research until ethical and scientific issues have been resolved;
- (3)
- principled international and domestic regulation; or
- (4)
- a laissez-faire approach (Bosley et al. 2015, pp. 383–85).
Their view of the regulated entity is no longer dominated by negative conceptions of an entity that needs to be curtailed and compelled to comply with minimum legal standards. With the diamond, the conception that pervaded responsive regulation theory is moderated by the understanding that regulated entities can also exceed such standards, and positively contribute to addressing the societal problem in question.
- (1)
- As highlighted in Section 4 of this article, the entirety of the UNESCO bioethical and human genome soft law framework is based on those foundational concepts. By mirroring those principles in a regulatory framework, it connects the legitimacy of UNESCO policy to the evolving international scientific and ethical practice (Somsen 2009, p. 114). Whilst there is no univocal ethic espoused in the Declarations, by and large the prevailing values are dignitarian and well suited to the current issue.
- (2)
- An underlying ethic that focuses on the concept of human dignity as a constraint on autonomy is ‘not only the most suitable for a liberal deliberative democracy’ as in today’s globalised society (Somsen 2009, p. 114), but is also the only possible answer to the reality of the disability community’s disadvantaged position vis-à-vis continuous and rapid scientific advances like CRISPR (Fukuyama 1992; Brownsword 2004). The human rights model of disability is strongly complemented by, and shares largely the same objectives as, the idea of inherent human dignity. If the two ideas work in tandem, persons with disabilities will have the best chance at enacting beneficial reform at both international and national levels.
- (3)
- A system of human rights and dignity has the potential to be flexible and adaptive to future technological change through the articulation of new international human rights principles specific to gene editing. The common acceptance of its underlying principles would also assist in its quick adoption by national regulatory agencies and parliaments (Mathews et al. 2015, p. 160). Whilst there is a considerable challenge in ensuring that such a regime is articulated clearly enough to be meaningful whilst not so broadly as to be arbitrary (Somsen 2009, p. 115), it is arguably the best theoretical framework at this point in time.
5.2. The Way There
Principles generally serve to motivate people to do the things that seem good and right, but without the constraints and external pressure of specific rules. Introduce specific regulations on the safety and efficacy of gene editing and that starts to infringe on people’s ethical limits, which traditional medical product regulation is not designed to address.
A productive next step might be to have a high-level task force representing the full range of constituencies with major stakes in these issues undertake a comprehensive review and assessment of options for global oversight and regulation.
- (1)
- safeguarding and promoting individual health and wellbeing;
- (2)
- cautiously approaching novel technologies in response to consistently changing information;
- (3)
- respecting individual rights;
- (4)
- warding against undesirable social consequences; and
- (5)
- equally and equitably distributing information, burdens and benefits (National Academies of Sciences and Medicine 2017, p. 23).
- (1)
- Promoting wellbeing: this principle aims to prevent harm by applying genome editing technologies to increase health and wellbeing whilst ensuring a reasonable balance of risk and benefit for any such application;
- (2)
- Transparency: this principle encourages the free flow of information between stakeholders, including full, frank and timely disclosure and meaningful public input and debate in all aspects of policymaking for CRISPR and related technologies;
- (3)
- Due care: this principle requires careful and deliberate conduct by researchers in relation to their patients, including appropriate supervision and consistent reassessment of risks, advances in technology and medicine, and cultural opinions;
- (4)
- Responsible science: this principle serves to set and maintain high research standards in compliance with the norms of international society and the profession. This includes quality research design, review and evaluation, transparency, and the correction of false or misleading data or analysis;
- (5)
- Respect for persons: this principle necessitates cognisance of the inherent human dignity of all people and the freedom of and respect for personal choice. Genetic characteristics are not indicative of any greater or lesser moral value. Further, respect for persons embodies active commitments to prevent neo-eugenics movements akin to the past, and to destigmatise disability;
- (6)
- Fairness: this principle obliges us to treat all equally, including in distributing risks and benefits of research and enabling the equitable access to resulting clinical applications of human gene editing;
- (7)
- Transnational cooperation: this principle highlights the immense need for collaboration in both research and regulation, whilst accommodating for different cultural perspectives. Adherence requires, where possible, coordination of international regulatory standards and processes, and data sharing between scientific communities and regulatory authorities.
- A 2002 proposal, which called for a ‘Convention on the Preservation of the Human Species’, aimed to prohibit human reproductive cloning and human germline genetic modification, and establish national oversight systems that ensured that use of gametes or embryos met consent, safety and ethical standards (Annas et al. 2002).
- A 2007 proposal, which asserted that the concept of a complete ban on human reproductive cloning had essentially attained the status of customary international law, to codify this into an international instrument under the UNESCO framework (Kuppuswamy et al. 2007).
- A 2008 proposal, which posited a ‘Genetic Heritage Safeguard Treaty’ based on the 1970 Nuclear Nonproliferation Treaty, to serve the dual function of both encouraging responsible applications of human genetic research as well as delineating limits on those applications deemed ‘undesirable’ (Metzl 2008).
6. Conclusions
Conflicts of Interest
References
- Altman, Russ B., Shamik Mascharak, and Niklaus Evitt. 2015. Human Germline Crispr-Cas Modification: Toward a Regulatory Framework. American Journal of Bioethics 15: 25–29. [Google Scholar]
- Amundson, Ron, and Shari Tresky. 2008. Bioethics and Disability Rights: Conflicting Values and Perspectives. Bioethical Inquiry 5: 111–23. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Annas, George J., Lori B. Andrews, and Rosario M. Isasi. 2002. Protecting the Endangered Human: Toward an International Treaty Prohibiting Cloning and Inheritable Alterations. American Journal of Law & Medicine 28: 151–78. [Google Scholar]
- Araki, Motoko, and Tetsuya Ishii. 2014. International Regulatory Landscape and Integration of Corrective Genome Editing into in Vitro Fertilization. Reproductive Biology and Endocrinology 12: 108. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
- Asch, Adrienne. 2000. Why I Haven’t Changed My Mind about Prenatal Diagnosis: Reflections and Refinements. Prenatal Testing and Disability Rights. Edited by Erik Parens and Adrienne Asch. Washington: Georgetown University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Ayres, Ian, and John Braithwaite. 1992. Responsive Regulation: Transcending the Deregulation Debate. Oxford: Oxford University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Bachruch, Susan. 2004. In the Name of Public Health—Nazi Racial Hygeine. New England Journal of Medicine 351: 417–20. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
- Baker, Beth. 2016. The Ethics of Changing the Human Genome. BioScience 66: 267–73. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Baldi, Pierre. 2001. The Shattered Self: The End of Natural Evolution. Cambridge: MIT Press. [Google Scholar]
- Baltimore, David, Paul Berg, Michael Botchan, Dana Carroll, R. Alta Charo, George Church, Jacob E. Corn, George Q. Daley, Jennifer A. Doudna, Marsha Fenner, and et al. 2015. A Prudent Path Forward for Genomic Engineering and Germline Gene Modification. Science 348: 36–38. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
- Baruch, Susannah, Audrey Huang, Daryl Pritchard, Andrea Kalfoglou, Gail Javitt, Rick Borchelt, Joan Scott, and Kathy Hudson. 2005. Human Germline Genetic Modification: Issues and Options for Policymakers. Baltimore: Genetics and Public Policy Center, Johns Hopkins University Berman Institute of Bioethics. [Google Scholar]
- Basser, Lee Ann. 2011. Human Dignity. In Critical Perspectives on Human Rights and Disability Law. Edited by Marcia H. Rioux, Lee Ann Basser and Melinda Jones. Leiden: Martinus Nijhoff Publishers, pp. 17–36. [Google Scholar]
- Benjamin, Ruha. 2016. Interrogating Equity: A Disability Justice Approach to Genetic Engineering. Issues in Science & Technology 32: 50–54. [Google Scholar]
- Bennett, Rebecca. 2009. The Fallacy of the Principle of Procreative Beneficence. Bioethics 23: 265–73. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
- Black, Edwin. 2008. War against the Weak: Eugenics and America’s Campaign to Create a Master Race. New York: Dialog Press. [Google Scholar]
- Black, Julia. 2002. Critical Reflections on Regulation. Australian Journal of Legal Philosophy 27: 1–46. [Google Scholar]
- Bosley, Katrine S., Michael Botchan, Annelien L. Bredenoord, Dana Carroll, R. Alta Charo, Emmanuelle Charpentier, Ron Cohen, Jacob Corn, Jennifer Doudna, Guoping Feng, and et al. 2015. Crispr Germline Engineering—The Community Speaks. Nature Biotechnology 33: 478–86. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
- Breggin, Peter. 1993. Psychiatry’s Role in the Holocaust. International Journal of Risk & Safety in Medicine 4: 133–48. [Google Scholar]
- Brosius, Jurgen, and Martin Kreitman. 2000. Eugenics—Evolutionary Nonsense? Nature Genetics 25: 253. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
- Brownsword, Roger. 2004. What the World Needs Now: Techno-Regulation, Human Rights and Human Dignity. In Global Governance and the Quest for Justice. Edited by Roger Brownsword. Oxford: Hart Publishing, p. 203. [Google Scholar]
- Brownsword, Roger. 2009. Human Dignity, Ethical Pluralism, and the Regulation of Modern Biotechnologies. In New Technologies and Human Rights. Edited by Thérèse Murphy. New York: Oxford University Press, pp. 19–84. [Google Scholar]
- Burleigh, Michael. 1994. Death and Deliverance: ‘Euthanasia’ in Germany, C.1900 to 1945. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Center for Genetics and Society. 2015. Human Germline Modification: Summary of National and International Policies. Berkeley: Centre for Genetics and Society. [Google Scholar]
- Center for Genetics and Society and Friends of the Earth. 2015. Extreme Genetic Engineering and the Human Future: Reclaiming Emerging Biotechnologies for the Common Good. Berkeley: Center for Genetics and Society. [Google Scholar]
- Council for Responsible Genetics. 2005. Position Paper on Human Germline Manipulation. Cambridge: Council for Responsible Genetics. [Google Scholar]
- Degener, Theresia. 2014. A Human Rights Model of Disability. Available online: http://www.academia.edu/18181994/A_human_rights_model_of_disability (accessed on 10 June 2016).
- Degener, Theresia, and Gerard Quinn. 2002. Survey of International, Comparative and Regional Disability Law Reform. In Disability Rights Law and Policy: International and National Perspectives. Edited by Silvia Yee and Mary Lou Breslin. Leiden: Martinus Nijhoff. [Google Scholar]
- Disabled Peoples International (DPI). 2000. Disabled People Speak on the New Genetics: DPI Europe Position Statement on Bioethics and Human Rights. London: DPI Europe. [Google Scholar]
- Doudna, Jennifer A. 2015. How Crispr Lets Us Edit Our DNA. London: TEDGlobal, Transcript. [Google Scholar]
- Dzau, Victor J., and Ralph J. Cicerone. 2015. Responsible Use of Human Gene-Editing Technologies. Human Gene Therapy 26: 411–12. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
- El-Zein, Souheil. 2008. International Regulation of Human Genetics. In Genetic Engineering and the World Trade System. Edited by Daniel Wuger and Thomas Cottier. New York: Cambridge University Press, p. 315. [Google Scholar]
- Esvelt, Kevin M., and Harris H. Wang. 2013. Genome-Scale Engineering for Systems and Synthetic Biology. Molecular Systems Biology 9: 641. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed] [Green Version]
- Finkelstein, Vic, and Ossie Stuart. 1996. Developing New Services. In Beyond Disability: Towards an Enabling Society. Edited by Gerard Hales. London: SAGE Publications. [Google Scholar]
- Fischer, Bernard A. 2012. Maltreatment of People with Serious Mental Illness in the Early 20th Century: A Focus on Nazi Germany and Eugenics in America. Journal of Nervous and Mental Disease 200: 1096–100. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
- French, Phillip. 1994. What Is Disability? In On Equal Terms—Working with Disabled People. Edited by Phillip French. Oxford: Butterworth-Heinemann. [Google Scholar]
- Fukuyama, Francis. 1992. The End of History and the Last Man. New York: Free Press. [Google Scholar]
- Fukuyama, Francis. 2002. Our Posthuman Future: Consequences of the Biotechnology Revolution. New York: Farrar, Strauss and Giroux. [Google Scholar]
- Galton, Francis. 1883. Inquiries into Human Faculty and Development. London: Macmillan. [Google Scholar]
- Grant, Evadné. 2007. Dignity and Equality. Human Rights Law Review 7: 299–329. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Harris, John. 1990. The Wrong of Wrongful Life. Journal of Law & Society 17: 90–105. [Google Scholar]
- Harris, John. 1998. Clones, Genes and Immortality: Ethics and the Genetic Revolution. Oxford: Oxford University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Hayes, Richard. Is There an Emerging International Consensus on the Proper Uses of the New Human Genetic Technologies? Paper presented at the US House of Representatives Foreign Affairs Committee Subcommittee on Terrorism, Nonproliferation and Trade Hearing on Genetics and Other Human Modification Technologies: Sensible International Regulations or a New Kind of Arms Race? Los Angeles, CA, USA, 19 June 2008. [Google Scholar]
- Herberer, Patricia. 2002. Targeting the “Unfit” and Radical Public Health Strategies in Nazi Germany. In Deaf People in Hitler’s Europe. Edited by Donna F. Ryan and John S. Schuchmann. Washinton: Gallaudet University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Hoge, Stephen K., and Paul S. Appelbaum. 2012. Ethics and Neuropsychiatric Genetics: A Review of Major Issues. International Journal of Neuropsychopharmacology 15: 1547–57. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
- Hsu, Patrick D., Eric S. Lander, and Fenc Zhang. 2014. Development and Applications of Crispr-Cas9 for Genome Engineering. Cell 157: 1262–78. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
- Ida, Ryuichi. 2003. Bioethics and International Law. In Ordine Internazionale E Valori Etici. Edited by Nerina Boschiero. Verona: Societa Italiana di Diritto Internazionale, p. 365. [Google Scholar]
- Iles, Alastair T. 1996. The Human Genome Project: A Challenge to the Human Rights Framework. Harvard Human Rights Journal 9: 27–60. [Google Scholar] [PubMed]
- Imparato, Andrew J. 2004. Testimony: Senate Hearing on Prenatal Genetic Testing Technology. Washington: United States Congress, Committee on Commerce, Science, and Transportation, Subcommittee on Science, Technology, and Space. [Google Scholar]
- International Bioethics Committee. 2015. Report of the Ibc on Updating Its Reflection on the Human Genome and Human Rights. Paris: UNESCO. [Google Scholar]
- Isasi, Rosario, Erika Kleiderman, and Bartha Maria Knoppers. 2016. Editing Policy to Fit the Genome? Science 351: 337–39. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
- Ishii, Tetsuya. 2015. Germ Line Genome Editing in Clinics: The Approaches, Objectives and Global Society. Briefings in Functional Genomics. Available online: http://bfg.oxfordjournals.org/content/early/2015/11/27/bfgp.elv053.full (accessed on 14 June 2016).
- Jones, Melinda. 2011a. Introduction: Dignity. In Critical Perspectives on Human Rights and Disability Law. Edited by Marcia H. Rioux, Lee Ann Basser and Melinda Jones. Leiden: Martinus Nijhoff Publishers, pp. 85–86. [Google Scholar]
- Jones, Melinda. 2011b. Valuing All Lives—Even “Wrongful” Ones. In Critical Perspectives on Human Rights and Disability Law. Edited by Marcia H. Rioux, Lee Ann Basser and Melinda Jones. Leiden: Martinus Nijhoff Publishers, pp. 87–116. [Google Scholar]
- Kayess, Rosemary, and Phillip French. 2008. Out of Darkness into Light? Introducing the Convention on the Rights of Persons with Disabilities. Human Rights Law Review 8: 1–34. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- King, David. 2001. Eugenic Tendencies in Modern Genetics. In Redesigning Life? The Worldwide Challenge to Genetic Engineering. Edited by Brian Tokar. London: Zed Books, pp. 171–81. [Google Scholar]
- Knoppers, Bartha Maria. 2016. Human Gene Editing: Principles & Precedents. Available online: http://nationalacademies.org/cs/groups/genesite/documents/webpage/gene_172445.pdf (accessed on 3 May 2017).
- Kolieb, Jonathan. 2015. When to Punish, When to Persuade and When to Reward: Strengthening Responsive Regulation with the Regulatory Diamond. Monash University Law Review 41: 136–63. [Google Scholar]
- Kuppuswamy, Chamundeeswari, Darryl Macer, Mihaela Serbulea, and Brendan Tobin. 2007. Is Human Reproductive Cloning Inevitable: Future Options for UN Governance. Tokyo: United Nations University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Lander, Eric S. 2015. Brave New Genome. New England Journal of Medicine 373: 5–8. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
- Lanphier, Edward, Fyodor Urnov, Sarah Ehlen Haecker, and Michael Werner. 2015. Don’t Edit the Human Germ Line. Nature 519: 410–11. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
- Ledford, Heidi. 2015. Crispr, the Disruptor. Nature 522: 20–24. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
- Lenzerini, Federico. 2006. Biotechnology, Human Dignity and the Human Genome. In Biotechnology and International Law. Edited by Francesco Francioni and Tullio Scovazzi. Portland: Hart Publishing, pp. 285–340. [Google Scholar]
- Liang, Puping, Yanwen Xu, Xiya Zhang, Chenhui Ding, Rui Huang, Zhen Zhang, Jie Lv, Xiaowei Xie, Yuxi Chen, Yujing Li, and et al. 2015. Crispr/Cas9-Mediated Gene Editing in Human Tripronuclear Zygotes. Protein & Cell 6: 363–72. [Google Scholar]
- Lindner, Ralf, Stefan Kuhlmann, Sally Randles, and Bjørn Bedsted. 2016. Navigating towards Shared Responsibility. Brussels: ResAGora. [Google Scholar]
- Marzano-Parisoli, Maria Michela. 2001. Disability, Wrongful-Life Lawsuits, and the Human Difference: An Exercise in Ethical Perplexity. Social Theory and Practice 27: 637–59. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Mathews, Debra J. H., Sarah Chan, Peter J. Donovan, Thomas Douglas, Christopher Gyngell, John Harris, Alan Regenberg, and Robin Lovell-Badge. 2015. Crispr: A Path through the Thicket. Nature 527: 159–61. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
- McCrudden, Christopher. 2008. Human Dignity and Judicial Interpretation of Human Rights. European Journal of International Law 19: 655–724. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [Green Version]
- McLean, Sheila, and Laura Williamson. 2007. Impairment and Disability: Law and Ethics at the Beginning and End of Life. London: Routledge. [Google Scholar]
- Menand, Louis. 2004. The Science of Human Nature and the Human Nature of Science. In Genetics, Disability, and Deafness. Edited by John Vickrey Van Cleve. Washington: Gallaudet University Press, pp. 5–22. [Google Scholar]
- Metzl, Jamie. 2008. Brave New World War. Center for Genetics and Society. Available online: http://www.geneticsandsociety.org/article.php?id=3985 (accessed on 1 June 2016).
- National Academies of Sciences and Medicine. 2015. On Human Gene Editing: International Summit Statement. Washington: National Academies of Sciences and Medicine. [Google Scholar]
- National Academies of Sciences and Medicine. 2017. Human Genome Editing: Science, Ethics, and Governance. Washington: National Academies Press. [Google Scholar]
- Oliver, Michael. 1990. The Politics of Disablement. Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan. [Google Scholar]
- Oliver, Michael. 1996. Understanding Disability: From Theory to Practice. New York: St. Martin’s Press. [Google Scholar]
- Parmenter, Trevor R. 2005. Are We Engineering Ourselves out of Existence? Journal of Intellectual and Developmental Disability 30: 53–56. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Parthasarathy, Shobita. 2016. Crispr Dispute Raises Bigger Patent Issues That We’re Not Talking about. The Conversation. April 4. Available online: https://theconversation.com/crispr-dispute-raises-bigger-patent-issues-that-were-not-talking-about-56715 (accessed on 13 June 2016).
- Peschin, Susan. 2017. How Should We Regulate Genome Editing? World Economic Forum. Available online: https://www.weforum.org/agenda/2017/05/how-should-we-regulate-genome-editing/ (accessed on 2 June 2017).
- Pollack, Robert. 2015. Eugenics Lurk in the Shadow of CRISPR. Science 348: 871. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
- President’s Council on Bioethics. 2003. Beyond Therapy: Biotechnology and the Pursuit of Happiness. Washington: President’s Council on Bioethics. [Google Scholar]
- Proctor, Robert N. 1988. Racial Hygeine: Medicine under the Nazis. Cambridge: Harvard University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Quinn, Gerard, and Theresia Degener. 2002. The Current Use and Future Potential Use of United Nations Human Rights Instruments in the Context of Disability. New York and Geneva: Office of the United Nations High Commissioner for Human Rights. [Google Scholar]
- Reaume, Denise G. 2002–2003. Discrimination and Dignity. Louisiana Law Review 63: 645–96. [Google Scholar]
- Reiss, Thomas. Governance Approaches for Human Gene Editing Based on Responsible Research and Innovation. Paper presented at the National Academies of Sciences and Medicine’s International Summit on Human Gene Editing, Washington, DC, USA, 1–3 December 2015. [Google Scholar]
- Samaha, Adam. 2007. What Good Is the Social Model of Disability? The University of Chicago Law Review 74: 166. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Sarewitz, Daniel. 2015. Crispr. Science Can’t Solve It. Nature 522: 413–14. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
- Savulescu, Julian, Jonathan Pugh, Thomas Douglas, and Christopher Gyngell. 2015. The Moral Imperative to Continue Gene Editing Research on Human Embryos. Protein & Cell 6: 476–79. [Google Scholar]
- Saxton, Marsha. 1988. Prenatal Screening and Discriminatory Attitudes About Disability. Women and Health 13: 217–24. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Shakespeare, Tom. 1995. Back to the Future? New Genetics and Disabled People. Critical Social Policy 44: 22–35. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
- Shakespeare, Tom. 2002. The Social Model of Disability: An Outdated Ideology? Research in Social Science and Disability 2: 9–28. [Google Scholar]
- Shakespeare, Tom. 2013. The Social Model of Disability. In The Disability Studies Reader. Edited by Lennard J. Davis. Abingdon: Routledge. [Google Scholar]
- Shakespeare, Tom. 2015. Gene Editing: Heed Disability Views. Nature 527: 446. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
- Singer, Peter. 1993. Practical Ethics, 2nd ed. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. [Google Scholar]
- Smith, George P., II. 2012. Law and Bioethics: Intersections Along the Mortal Coil. Abingdon: Routledge. [Google Scholar]
- Somsen, Han. 2009. Regulating Human Genetics in a Neo-Genetic Era. In New Technologies and Human Rights. Edited by Thérèse Murphy. New York: Oxford University Press, pp. 85–127. [Google Scholar]
- Thomas, Pam, Lorraine Gradwell, and Natalie Markham. 1997. Defining Impairment within the Social Model of Disability. Greater Manchester Coalition of Disabled People. Available online: http://disability-studies.leeds.ac.uk/files/library/thomas-pam-Defining-Impairment-within-the-Social-Model-of-Disability.pdf (accessed on 29 May 2016).
- Thompson, Charis. Governance, Regulation, and Control: Of Which People, by Which People, for Which People? Paper presented at the National Academies of Sciences and Medicine’s International Summit on Human Gene Editing, Washington, DC, USA, 1–3 December 2015. [Google Scholar]
- Turmusani, Majid. 2004. Genetic Technology and the UN Disability Convention. Disability World. Available online: http://www.disabilityworld.org/12-02_05/news/genetictech.shtml (accessed on 3 June 2016).
- UN Secretary General. 2006. Secretary-General Hails Adoption of Landmark Convention on Rights of People with Disabilities. SG/SM/10797-HR/4911-L/T/4400. December 3. Available online: http://www.un.org/press/en/2006/sgsm10797.doc.htm (accessed on 8 June 2016).
- United Nations. 2007. UN Convention on the Rights of Persons with Disabilities, opened for signature 30 March 2007, 999 UNTS 3 (entered into force 3 May 2008). [Google Scholar]
- Walters, LeRoy. 1978. Bioethics as Field of Ethics. In Contemporary Issues in Bioethics. Edited by Tom L. Beauchamp and LeRoy Walters. Los Angeles: Calif Dickenson, p. 49. [Google Scholar]
- Witzany, Guenther. 2016. No Time to Waste on the Road to a Liberal Eugenics? EMBO Reports 17: 281. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
- Wolbring, Gregor. 2015. Gene Editing: Govern Ability Expectations. Nature 527: 446. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef] [PubMed]
- Wolbring, Gregor, and Lucy Diep. 2016. The Discussions around Precision Genetic Engineering: Role of and Impact on Disabled People. Laws 5: 37. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
1 | Responsible Research and Innovation in a Distributed Anticipatory Governance Frame. A Constructive Socionormative Approach. |
© 2017 by the author. Licensee MDPI, Basel, Switzerland. This article is an open access article distributed under the terms and conditions of the Creative Commons Attribution (CC BY) license (http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/).
Share and Cite
Conti, A. Drawing the Line: Disability, Genetic Intervention and Bioethics. Laws 2017, 6, 9. https://doi.org/10.3390/laws6030009
Conti A. Drawing the Line: Disability, Genetic Intervention and Bioethics. Laws. 2017; 6(3):9. https://doi.org/10.3390/laws6030009
Chicago/Turabian StyleConti, Adam. 2017. "Drawing the Line: Disability, Genetic Intervention and Bioethics" Laws 6, no. 3: 9. https://doi.org/10.3390/laws6030009
APA StyleConti, A. (2017). Drawing the Line: Disability, Genetic Intervention and Bioethics. Laws, 6(3), 9. https://doi.org/10.3390/laws6030009