1. Introduction
“Why workers’ rights are not women’s rights” is an argument whose purpose is to make clear that workers’ rights rest on a masculine embodiment of the labor subject, and it is this masculine embodiment that is at the center of employment contracts and employment relations systems. By excavating the gender subjects implicit to and explicit in regulations of labor, the paper reveals the opposition of paired terms, masculinity and femininity, privileging production over reproduction and naturalizing gender-based power relations, and identifies various laboring activities associated with differential rights and responsibilities. An examination of the treatment of part-time employment and waged caring labor, framed in labor, welfare, immigration, and citizenship policies and practices, locates exclusions from labor standards and exemptions from entitlements due to eligibility requirements and thresholds that assume the masculine embodiment of the worker-citizen.
The feminist analytics used in this paper highlights how the tension between inclusionary and exclusionary principles impacts on the capability of women workers to make claims on and to exercise rights in a political community [
1]. Policies and laws draw boundaries of what constitutes work and who is recognized as a worker worthy of rights and social protections. A feminist lens also deciphers an apparent paradox; why gender unequal outcomes result despite the application of gender-neutral principles. An equal treatment frame aimed at formal equality in the labor market founders without addressing inequality of circumstances between men and women, and among differently positioned women with regard to the work of social reproduction. For this reason, legal protections and workers’ rights solely based on the wage-relation in general, and standard employment more specifically, neither guarantee nor necessarily foster egalitarian social relations that are either class or gender-based.
Gendering the analysis illustrates how contemporary labor laws and conventions grant rights on the basis of, and to, a rather abstract conception of the prototypical worker-citizen. Its origins lie in what classical political economy labeled a capitalist logic, as well as the historical practices in which free class agents entered into contracts for continuous, full-time work, free of care responsibilities outside of the wage/labor nexus. Thus, it is this particular abstract construction of the proto-typical worker which instantiates the separation of “rights to” from “responsibilities for”, and it is this separation that allows the masculine embodiment of the labor subject. Modes of regulation privileging rights over responsibilities will valorize the masculine worker-citizen whose rights derive from their participation in wage labor and simultaneously devalue the feminine worker who is directly connected to caring labor.
The paper argues that framing of “rights to” as separated from “responsibilities for” in labor laws and employment regulations has disqualified some categories of work and workers from social protections, and has disadvantaged women from claiming rights as workers. Three examples highlight relevant issues in relation to: (i) paid home care work; (ii) transnational care work; and (iii) part-time work. The first example examines unequal treatment of US female home care workers denied basic workers’ rights because their responsibilities for care of the elderly are deemed casual labor outside of labor standards. The second reviews immigration laws and citizenship policies finding that universal claims for workers’ rights by women engaged in care labor are complicated by the lack of enforcement mechanisms within and between states, and by the failure of national states to assume responsibility for ensuring workers’ rights of and offering adequate social protections to female migrant workers employed in their territorial jurisdiction. The third considers the equal treatment frame prominent in regulations of labor: both the European Union (EU) and the International Labor Organization (ILO) have promulgated employment policies and conventions to address women’s inferior position in paid labor, while issues related to responsibilities for social reproduction remain stubbornly within the purview of domestic politics.
Finally, deconstructing gendered subjects and key words in regulations of labor is a feminist project for orienting political action that can wed workers’ rights to women’s rights. The paper revisits socialist-feminist and feminist standpoint theories’ insight that reproductive labor, particularly household caring labor, is both a locus of exploitation and a site from which resistant subjects and alternative visions might emerge [
2]. A new feminist politics focused on both “rights to” and shared “responsibilities for” can dislodge the prototypical masculine worker-citizen from dominating legal protections, and can frame alternative political imaginaries tying together a feminist politics of recognition to a labor politics of redistribution. Unless “rights to” and “responsibilities for” principles are co-constitutive frames of reference, workers’ rights alone will not realize gender equality and justice.
2. Rights to versus Responsibilities for: Framing Regulations of Labor
Frames of reference in regulation of labor privilege rights accorded to the wage labor subject without responsibilities for care. In capitalist societies, waged work is seen “as a moral duty, as life’s most noble calling, and as the necessary center of social rights and citizenship” [
3]. Citizenship confers exclusive rights and duties to an individual
vis-à-vis a sovereign state, whereas the more expansive social rights extends “entitlements [including welfare and social wages] enjoyed by citizens and are enforced by courts within the national framework of a sovereign state” ([
4], p. 167). More specifically, labor regulations codify basic rights and benefits to a worker-citizen based on formal participation in the waged labor force.
Labor regulations and laws govern employment relationships, including both implicit and explicit contractual rights and obligations, are both class- and gender-based. In general, labor regulations constrain an unfettered capitalist marketplace, imposing rules on “the exercise of discretion by those with market or institutional power” ([
5], p. 1), which can significantly modify both employer and union behavior ([
6], p. 5). Yet, employers’ prerogatives render some subjects out-of-bounds from regulation. Fundamentally, labor law assumes that the individual enters the labor market free of responsibilities for care. Since women are charged with this responsibility for childcare (reproduction) and household maintenance (consumption), they do not enter the labor market as free rational agents like men do [
7]. In this way, the labor subject in regulations is already gendered. Much of labor law and employment regulation derives labor standards based on the hetero-normative masculine embodiment of the labor subject who is presumed to engage in waged work without interruptions for care responsibility.
Since the 1930s, Fordist labor regulations standardized benefits around an implicit male work biography of continuous employment paying a family-wage, a set of social benefits and entitlements, and regulatory protections in a national context ([
8], p. 10). A system of legally binding agreements, centralized and coordinated bargaining along with a network of laws reinforced what Muckenberger (1989) has called the standard employment relationship or SER (
Normalarbeitsverhaeltnis). This relationship was built on and assumed a gender division of labor in which a male-breadwinner would provide financial support while a female-care giver would perform unpaid domestic labor to sustain the family. Contractually, those workers, either male or female, who deviate from this standard, suffer penalties in terms of foregone promotions and training, lost earnings, limited pensions, and a risk of social exclusion. Temporally, time thresholds, imposed as a basis of qualification for benefits, exclude or differentially include nonstandard employment from regulation or subject them to different and often inferior protection. For example, fair labor standards regulation basing eligibility against a historically negotiated standard work schedule withholds overtime pay from many nonstandard workers when calculating their overall working time. Regulatory measures and labor law frameworks do not adequately grasp or respond to fragmented temporal features such as unpredictable hours, long and split shifts, periods of on-call duty, that are typical of domestic work ([
9], p. 513). Labor regulations fashioned around a prototypical masculine worker-citizen as the implicit norm for and the basis of explicit rights to employment protections and entitlements have disregarded responsibility for care
1.
Labor laws discursively and materially accord differential rights across categories of work and workers, either through exclusion altogether or through exemption from a range of entitlements. All non-waged workers fall outside labor law jurisdiction, are classified as non-employed and therefore ineligible for rights associated with wage employment. Some waged workers enjoy differential treatment because of their employment status (as informal labor) and/or because of their worker’s status (as a welfare recipient, as a prisoner, or as a non-citizen). Regardless of the number of years worked and the intensity of their labor, informal labor does not qualify for most employment-related entitlements. More generally, there are legal boundary markers differentiating rights and obligations based on categorical differences created and enforced by jurisdictions. “Jurisdiction sorts the where [territory], the who [authority], the what, and the how of governance…” [
10]. These jurisdictions can create “different bundles of rights and responsibilities for similar activities”
2, in part, because the status of the worker or the labor activity can cross “a number of jurisdictional boundaries between nation states, different areas of law and different levels [and agencies] of government within a nation” ([
11], p. 237). Within the national state, agencies (e.g., welfare, immigration, and prisons) issue their own “labor rules” that apply different labor standards based on the classification of the work and workers [
12]; for example, workfare rules derive from welfare agencies and guest workers come under the jurisdiction of immigration laws. Each agency determines its own labor rules and their associated rights: for example, who and what types of work are worthy of protection; what claims can be made and by whom; and what labor activities are deserving of legal recognition. More specifically, welfare policies and agencies dictate work conditions and contractual rights that may not comply with general labor standards law, such as mandatory workfare programs that force welfare recipients to work in jobs that may pay subminimum wages. Likewise, the domain of immigration law and citizenship requirements determines the lives and livelihoods of non-citizens working in a bounded national territory. Immigration law may allow for the issuing of special work visas stipulating different workers’ rights based on their legal status rather than on the nature of their work performed. Altogether, various jurisdictions construct the standard worker so that some categories of work and workers, both paid and unpaid, do not enjoy the same entitlements and rights.
Determining which area of law, which government agency, and which level of the government(s) (state, provincial, federal, national, transnational) oversees the governance of a worker and the enforcement of her rights also can cause what Fudge calls “jurisdictional conundrums” ([
11], pp. 243–44). Judy Fudge identifies such conundrums arising from global care chains, employment agencies in the case of domestic migrant workers who perform live-in work in Canadian homes. Migrant domestic workers ‘transgress” jurisdictional boundaries; their status as temporary workers and as migrants complicates jurisdictional boundaries for claiming and exercising rights accorded by law, and exempts them from an array of labor (working time) and gender regulations (such as childcare subsidies, maternity leave). She goes on the show that: “The objects of governance—what is to be regulated—whether domestic work is a matter of family law or employment law or whether migrant workers fall within immigration or labor law—are associated with governance technologies (how the object should be governed), which in turn, can be understood in terms of institutional capacities and rationalities” ([
11], p. 243). Jurisdictional conundrums describe conflicts and tensions over institutional responsibilities for legal governance.
Women working full-time, full-year in so-called standard employment also encounter differential treatment than men, on average earning lower wages, enjoying fewer opportunities for overtime pay, seniority benefits, and promotional/training. In general, labor regulations, by legal statute and/or by collective bargaining agreements, have fallen short in fostering women’s rights. Labor regulation, buttressed by the implementation and the enforcement of affirmative action, sexual harassment, maternity leave, and other gender-specific regulations, improves women’s economic standing, but will not undo vertical and horizontal sex segregation that places women in disadvantageous and inferior positions relative to men in the economy. These laws have not eliminated barriers that impede women’s autonomy and empowerment, in part because they lack strong provisions and enforcement mechanisms and in part because the image of the “ideal” worker conflicts with cultural assumptions and stereotypes that deem parenting a female function. In these ways, the masculine worker-citizen conferring rights without responsibilities for care remains at the heart of labor law.
Relational Perspectives: Framing Rights and Responsibilities
Feminist legal scholarship has critically assessed conventional conceptions of “rights” in theory and in practice. New approaches direct attention to the difference between formal and substantive dimensions of equality [
12,
13,
14], and propose a sociological account of rights as relational [
15]. In their introduction to the special themed issue on “elusive equalities”, the editors recall Sandra Fredman’s multidimensional concept of substantive equality, including: (i) a redistributive dimension; (ii) a recognition dimension; (iii) a transformative dimension; and (iv) a participative dimension. Their example illustrates why the formal concept of equal rights, even if embedded in a substantive right, such as affirmative action policies, will not achieve equality of outcomes on these four dimensions if the policy, as in this case, does not address the structural disadvantages (wage hierarchies) that give rise to inequalities ([
14], p. 422). More broadly, equality between men and women does not necessarily erase inequalities, such as class and racial inequalities amongst women and increasing inequality for men [
14]. From such a sociological perspective, rights can be viewed as relational. Jennifer Nedelsky frames a relational approach to the conception of rights and laws: “What rights do and have always done is construct [social] relationships—such as those of power, responsibility, trust, and obligation”([
15], p. 231) that can either foster or undermine an individual’s ability to exercise autonomy ([
16], pp. 148–49). Rights can be assessed in terms of whether they promote the realization of core values (such as equality, security, freedom, responsibilities) in interpersonal relationships (see [
17], p. 333). Distinguishing the formal and the substantive dimensions of equality and articulating a relational theory of rights advance approaches attuned to social consequences and social contexts by considering what rights do.
The argument outlined here is compatible with the relational approach, and takes note of the substantive dimensions of equality. These approaches subsume responsibilities in their notion of “what rights do”: rights reference legal claims that structure relationships of power, responsibility and care. My alternative suggests that responsibilities for is a core social value and a key principle governing interpersonal relationships (both paid and unpaid) and demarcating institutionalized social relationships in and between the political, economic and family spheres. “Responsibilities for” require and assume that individuals take others into account. Shared responsibilities, more specifically, emphasize the social structures and practices that go into the daily and intergenerational maintenance of the working population (social reproduction) and the social relationships inherent to taking care of and caring for others. This conception of shared responsibilities encompasses but goes beyond the notion of personal responsibilities—a common rhetorical expression in liberal discourses. I caution when “responsibilities for”, are divorced from “rights to”, can lapse into paternalism. Historically, in colonial regimes, ruling elites assumed the posture of patrimonial authority over a conquered population. The archetypical patrimonial relationship of master and servant bound the servant “to [the family] by ties of affection, loyalty, and dependence” [
18]. As dependents in this context, servants did not have an independent status for grounding rights
3.
Taken in tandem, labor laws and welfare policies exhibit ambivalence with respect to the rights associated with responsibilities for different types of dependency. Dependents derive rights on the basis of their potential (youth), current (unemployed) and former (retired workers) position vis-à-vis the waged labor market. At the same time, others’ rights are derived from their status as mothers, as wives, as children, as the elderly, or as welfare recipient. For example, retired workers’ dependence on the state is viewed differently than welfare recipients’ dependency. In the first instance, the state guarantees, to different extents, retired workers’ right to a pension. Pensions are a negotiated benefit deferring income until the worker reaches an age threshold, either determined by a collective agreement and/or a labor law. In the second, a welfare recipients’ dependence is stigmatized. The current rhetoric in the US chastises welfare recipients for their dependence on the state, attenuates their right to long-term support (imposing limits on the amount of time for receipt of welfare over one’s lifetime, establishing restrictive criteria for eligibility to receive benefits, and requiring work among those deemed able-bodied), and emphasizes their personal responsibility for finding a long-term solution in the labor market rather than being guaranteed rights to a basic income. More ambivalently, mothers may receive an allowance for taking care of children; this responsibility is given standing in the law as an allowance rather than income reserved as a right. In other words, not all dependencies and responsibilities around care are treated equally.
Valorization of the wage labor relation and its masculine embodiment in much of labor regulation is premised on the gender “opposition of independence/dependence [which] maps onto other valued hierarchical oppositions: masculine/feminine, public/private, success/love, individual/community, economy/family, and [rational/emotional] ([
19], p. 322). By extension, the wage labor relation symbolically is connected to meanings of fatherhood and motherhood and their corresponding rights and responsibilities. More specifically, labor regulations and social policies treat men as independent wage earners not as dependent caretakers; “as rights-earning individuals not as needy family members; and as beneficiaries of cash benefits (unstigmatized) not as recipients of (unearned) services” ([
20], p. 464). The opposition between paired terms, symbolically, discursively, and culturally privilege “masculinity—not necessarily men—[which] is key to naturalizing the (symbolic, discursive, cultural, corporeal, material, economic) power relations that constitute multiple forms of subordination and exploitation…feminist research documents the deeply sedimented normalization of gender as governing code, valorizing that which is characterized as masculine (reason, agency) at the expense of that which is stigmatized as feminine (emotion, dependence)” ([
21], p. 35). A mode of labor regulation and policy premised on independence over interdependence tends to valorize the masculine worker-citizen whose rights derive from their participation in wage labor and tends to devalue the feminine connected to responsibilities for care and caring labor.
Some policies incorporate shared responsibilities with workers’ rights. A relational reading of rights is possible in some labor-related laws, such as pension laws provide survivor benefits and pension sharing with a married partner, albeit excluding those intimate partnerships (same-sex relationships) not legally recognized. Though mediated through another person’s wages and through the relationship to another person, pensions are an example of legally enforced rights based on responsibilities. Many countries now provide a right to subsidized childcare (though some are means-tested such as in the US), and some countries have a highly developed social infrastructure for childcare (as in Sweden). Over the past several years, paid maternity leave has been replaced by parental leave, including father’s entitlements promoting the possibility of shared care responsibilities. Shared responsibilities can revalue social parenting, which is a prerequisite for gender equality in the labor market. However, long duration on leave can have deleterious effects on wages and mobility, though the effect is mediated by policy regimes and institutional factors (see [
22]). The masculine embodiment of the labor subject remains a dominant frame of reference, and this implicit assumption is consequential for the realization of substantive rights and shared responsibilities.
3. Unequal Treatment: Responsibilities without Rights among Home Care Workers
Labor laws result in unequal treatment among workers whose labor responsibilities do not fit the classification of a worker deserving of rights. One of the most disadvantaged categories of work is performed by paid home care workers who are denied rights as workers, as women, and often, as citizens
4. In the US this occupational category owed its existence to welfare policies enacted during the New Deal administration. At the outset, home care was part of public relief assistance to the poor, both for clients who received care and for caregivers who were unemployed. Home care was designed to assist indigent elderly and disabled people, and directed at poor African American women who were hired to fill the bulk of these jobs. Its welfare designation stigmatized the service and the service providers by defining the labor activity as an unearned benefit rather than as work deserving rights. The discourse and the corresponding welfare policies disparaged both home care clients and workers for their dependence on the state, and promoted waged work as the means of gaining independence and rehabilitating poor women of color
5. Through the welfare channel, this workforce took on the cast of helpers responsible for care and not rights-bearing individuals.
US labor law reinforced the inferior status of this largely female workforce by excluding home care from labor standards (such as minimum wages and over-time pay) and social security. Home care workers’ ineligibility stemmed from their classification as housekeepers and as companions instead of as workers. Throughout, amendments of labor standards law continued to exclude home care workers, analogizing home care with casual baby-sitters, and so deemed different from real workers. The legal basis for the exclusion was the “companion exemption”, which applied across the board, exempting for-profit agencies from compliance with labor standards requirements. In 2013 the Obama Administration issued a labor ruling that extended minimum wage and overtime protection to the almost 2 million home care aides ([
23], p. 214), but took the unusual step of delaying the effective date until 1 January 2015 [
24], which coincides with the all-Republican Congress that can reverse the rule
6.
A recent court decision overturned the US Labor Department’s new rules that would have required agencies and families employing home care aids for the elderly and the disabled, to pay at least the federal minimum wage and overtime; this would have ended the 1974 regulation labeling these workers as “companions”. In this case, the presiding judge reasoned that only Congress could remove the companionship label and sided with the industry’s position that equated home care aids with occasional babysitters.
The New York Times’ editorial questioned the rationale applied, citing a unanimous 2007 Supreme Court decision that “Congress intended its broad grant of definitional authority …to include the authority to answer these kinds of questions”. This court decision may only delay the ruling ([
25], p. 8), yet an entrenched and unstated gender bias continues to influence assumptions regarding the boundaries and the definition of work and associated rights. On the one hand, the new rules acknowledge that labor activities, such as responsibilities for bathing, cooking and cleaning, entitle home care workers to receive minimum wages and overtime. On the other hand, boundary markers still relegate some aspects of care work to the status of companionship or non-work. For example, the new rules exclude time spent sleeping at a client’s home from labor standards. However, an aide sleeping at a client’s home may be called upon at any time to perform a service. By contrast, the law recognizes breaks/naps taken by workers in male-typed occupations, such as doctors, fire-fighters, and police officers (so prevalent among police that the activity earns the sobriquet of cooping); time taken off for naps on-the-job are a legally accepted part of their work effort during their work schedule.
Even countries that recognize citizens’ right to care services do not always accord equal compensation and the same rights to waged workers performing home care work and personal services in households. Much of this work is considered casual or informal labor ineligible for both social protections and a range of citizenship entitlements. In the EU domestic workers employed in private homes, even when covered by other labor laws, fall outside the ambit of working condition norms enumerated in the EU Working Time and Pregnancy Workers’ Directives ([
9], p. 512). Working time regimes tend to exclude domestic workers from coverage because their fluctuating and unpredictable work schedules deviate from the standard work schedule at the core of labor standards law. The actual conditions of domestic work and among workers depend on the welfare, care and migration regimes (e.g., how they entered the country, the nature of their legal status, the specific provisions of the work arrangement, and the jurisdictional resolution to conflicting provisions of different laws and policies). Generally, labor law devalues the labor and the labor activity among those responsible for home-based care work. The case of waged home care work shows how women’s responsibilities for care have been excluded from eligibility for claiming a host of workers’ rights.
4. Citizenship and Immigration: Women’s Rights versus Workers’ Rights
Today, many home care workers are migrants, either moving from less developed areas in their home countries or traveling long distances across national borders, primarily from the global South to the global North. The highly contested policy and politics around immigration and citizenship point to the dilemmas posed by, and the tension between workers’ rights and gender equality projects. Citizenship, and more accurately non-citizenship, divides women who may occupy the same territorial and even intimate spaces, yet who occupy different social locations. The model of citizenship has frequently been predicated on the increased availability of externalized and/or professionalized care services. Much of the redistribution of care has taken place between different groups of women, both within Western societies and on a global scale ([
26], p. 534). The liberal discourse of universal rights conflicts with the prevailing insular, nationalist notions of citizenship. “Liberal discourses of equality and inclusion are left to citizenship law while immigration law performs the dirty work of inequality and exclusion” (Danvergene, cited in [
27], p. 11). Practically and legally, citizenship stands “for an (at least relative) ethic of closure” ([
28], p. 136). Immigration policies similarly define an inside and an outside for the recognition of rights in a bounded political space. An examination of citizenship and immigration policies and practices highlights how tension between inclusionary and exclusionary principles defining entitlements impacts on the capability of differently positioned women workers to make claims on, expect responsibilities for, and to exercise rights in a political community.
4.1. Transnational Gendered Work, National Citizenship Rights
The practical and conceptual basis of citizenship is built on the assumption of an exclusionary bounded political community in contradistinction to universalistic claims of inclusiveness. Such bounded notions mark as “other” or as “foreign” those deemed outside the political community. This “ethic of closure” assumes and reifies boundaries that do not only operate at the “territorial-edge of a nation”, but also “within the territorial interior” ([
28], p. 136). In general, citizenship designates “distinct practices and institutions” and describes the “quality of relationships among members of a political community and the rules associated with the constitution and maintenance of community membership” ([
28], pp. 128–29). A form of industrial citizenship, forged by trade unions, limits rights to workers designated by collective bargaining agreements either industry-wide (as in Germany) or firm-based (as in Japan). In both cases, rights are not equally enjoyed by everyone presently working, citizen and non-citizen alike, in the same territorial space.
A broad notion of citizenship moves from one that distinctly refers to political engagement to one that encompasses economic justice ([
28], p. 130), as realized by a universal right to decent work promulgated by the ILO. It frames questions such as: who is a citizen, what rights attach to citizenship, and what are the boundaries of citizenship? Feminists go further to make visible the “linkages between women’s citizenship and the demands of social reproduction” ([
28], p. 131). But feminists and non-feminists alike tend to uncritically view the national society “as the total universe of analytical focus and normative concern” ([
28], p. 140)
7. Importantly, the failure to acknowledge the transnational scale of production and increasingly of reproduction, particularly transnational care chains has implications for citizenship as an “aspirational” concept in feminist theory and practice.
Increasing commodification and transnationalization of domestic and reproductive work reveals the “divided nature of citizenship” ([
28], p. 127). Citizenship performs double duty: it affirms a commitment against subordination and toward inclusion; and it is in the service of subordination and exclusion [
28]. In the first sense, feminists have called for women’s participation in the public sphere of paid labor as a means of achieving “full and equal ‘citizenship’” ([
28], p. 128). At the same time, feminists’ attempts to engender concepts of citizenship and to achieve “full-citizenship” rights falter when the transnational organization of domestic servitude and responsibilities for reproductive labor is not taken into account. As women enter paid labor outside of the home, they increasingly pay for reproductive services performed by migrant women, either in their homes or in the larger service economy (restaurants, laundries). Bosniak succinctly poses the problematic issue for feminism: “Achievement of citizenship for some women through the participation in paid work increasingly relies on labor of citizenship-less others” [
28]. In this way, citizenship or more accurately non-citizenship becomes an axis of inequality and exploitation, dividing women from the global North and global South. Yet, Bosniak cautions against the rhetorically tempting equation that “First World” women’s full citizenship is gained at the expense of “Third World” women’s denial of citizenship ([
28], p. 137). Exploitation of migrant women is not based on the appropriation or transfer of citizenship. Citizenship is not an object or “single quantity” transferable from some women to others. By contrast, care and more specifically love and affective labor, as Hochschild argues, represents a nonrenewable “good” or resource expropriated in a commercial exchange [
28]. This “is an exchange that is contingent upon economic inequality—international and domestic—and histories of gender and racial subordination, as well as upon the operation of national immigration controls” ([
28], pp. 137–38). Citizenship is divided to the extent that workers with citizenship enjoy different rights than non-citizens.
Non-citizenship accords different protections to workers present in the same political territory of a nation-state and strips migrant workers of avenues of redress. Migrant workers, especially those unauthorized to work in a country, are less able to exercise options of voice and even voluntary exit. The inherent vulnerability to deportation makes unauthorized migrant workers’ reluctant to invoke their inalienable human rights for fear of being reported. Deprived of state-sponsored income alternatives compounds fear of losing or leaving a job ([
28], p. 136), even in the face of abuse, for all migrants regardless of how they enter a country. The global dimension of care work highlights the “other” citizenship discourse of exclusion ([
28], p. 135).
All countries impose restrictions on rights and benefits of non-citizens, and most do not extend equal protections before the attainment of full-citizenship ([
29], p. 1135). However, eligibility for full-citizenship rights vary, ranging from more draconian laws denying any pathway to citizenship in migrant labor regimes in Singapore and in Dubai to more welcoming laws granting the possibility of citizenship after a specified length of time, such as the two-year waiting period in Spain and Canada. One notable example, the Canadian Live-in Caregiver Program, 1992, a special provision of the general Temporary Foreign Workers Program, is designed to attract qualified nurses as live-in workers for the elderly and the disabled
8. Under this program live-in caregivers receive an employment contract and a pathway to permanent residency. Though deemed a “best practice” program by the ILO, the law matches workers to a specific employer, restricting workers’ mobility in the labor market and their ability to seek better work opportunities, and leaving workers vulnerable to possible abuse by employers whose working conditions often escape the notice of federal and provincial governments because of their inadequate monitoring of program compliance ([
11], p. 248). In the US, lawful permanent residents enjoy some basic political and social rights ([
28], p. 136), yet so-called “illegal aliens” are ineligible for most state-sponsored benefits. As a consequence, their “irregular immigration status renders them vulnerable to subordination in a variety of arenas” ([
28], pp. 136–37), depriving workers of basic rights and disregarding responsibility for their social protections.
4.2. Immigration and Citizenship: Differential Workers’ Rights and Women’s Responsibilities
Immigration law “performs the dirty work of inequality and exclusion” (Danvergene, cited in [
27], p. 11) by regulating who can enter a country, specifying the length and terms of their stay, and restricting the location and type of jobs available. In particular, the introduction of guest worker programs creates a category of worker relegated to the tenuous legal status of “temporary settler” ([
29], p. 1135). Some of these programs restrict incorporation of migrants and often of their families, denying women migrants the ability to nurture their own families even as they are permitted to care for others in privileged families ([
29], p. 1134). Parrenas [
29] concludes that, “in this way receiving nations can secure a supply of low-wage workers who can be repatriated if the economy slows down”. Through immigration law, the state relinquishes responsibility for social reproduction of migrant labor and subjects migrants to different workers’ rights.
In Japan, relaxation of restrictive immigration policies and practices in the last decade of the 20th century, not coincidently during one of its worst economic crises and confronting a ticking time-bomb of an aging population, puts in sharp relief differential treatment of migrant workers and the divided nature of citizenship. Short-term programs for industrial training introduced in 1990, and technical internships permitted in 1993 created a pool of temporary labor ([
30], p. 66). These policy revisions served to induce migration of a relatively cheap female labor force without provoking too much political opposition from conservative members of the Diet or from the population at large ([
30], p. 66). Recruitment of Filipinas and Indonesian women on short-term training visas to perform health care guaranteed that women would fill these limited term contracts. The status of “trainee” deprived these workers of both explicit and implicit contractual commitments for continuous employment, and denied recognition of these workers’ actual skills, their previous work experience and their educational achievements, thereby enabling employers to pay lower wages. Moreover, the trainee program is part of a policy orientation in which Japan erects a “high wall” for “foreign labor” limiting their stay in the country [
31]. Short-term visas, like guest worker programs, function as revolving doors with legal requirements directing workers to return home after a fixed time period.
More generally, immigration policies and restrictions on pathways to citizenship permit differential treatment of migrant workers. Immigration law, as discussed above, restricts labor’s freedom of movement: where they can settle, the duration of their residence, and the type and conditions of work available to them. As a result, migrant labor often ends up in the lowest tiers of the labor market, and in precarious forms of employment. Because of the “illicit” nature of sex work and the isolation of much domestic work, many female migrants face extreme precariousness. This precariousness is not only produced by the informalized nature of the employment relationship and job characteristics, but also is inherent to the differential rights and protections accorded to non-citizens through immigration laws and restrictions on citizenship, that are further complicated by jurisdictional conundrums.
Overall, policies dealing with immigration and citizenship largely remain the purview of the nation-state, though the European Union relaxes their strict borders for members in the larger community. As a result, migrant labor may work in the shadows, unprotected by employment regulation in the country in which they reside yet out of reach of protections offered by the country of their origin. Political institutions and the realization of rights are relentlessly still located at the national and sub-national levels. Social protections and citizenship, unlike migrant labor, are not similarly mobile, but rather are realized and enforced by local and sometimes conflicting jurisdictions within nation-states and based on the male worker-citizen. Transnational domestic work troubles abstract, national-based definitions of citizenship formulated in law and in feminist theory. One of the few avenues for achieving full citizenship is to emulate the masculine embodiment of the labor subject by ceding responsibility for care/reproductive labor to low-wage workers, often women of color and migrant women. The example of transnationalization of waged domestic and reproductive work reveals the “divided nature of citizenship” ([
28], p. 127).
7. Conclusions: Can Workers’ Rights Ensure Women’s Rights?
The paper questioned why framings of workers’ rights do not translate into women’s rights. To answer this question the paper distinguished between “rights to” and “responsibilities for” in legal frames and discussed two different dimensions of “responsibilities for” in labor laws: the treatment of labor responsibilities of home care workers; and institutional responsibilities for the promulgation and enforcement of rights and shared responsibilities (jurisdictions). From the examples reviewed here, the framing of workers’ rights substantially and substantively derives from the standard employment relationship with its implicit reference to the masculine embodiment of the worker-citizen. Workers’ rights to social protections and entitlements without the recognition that unequal responsibilities for care tend to favor those who are able to offload responsibilities for social reproduction and tend to disadvantage those who perform these responsibilities, whether paid or unpaid. Moreover, there are different rights based on different responsibilities across categories of work and workers.
The first example discussed how US home care workers are at a triple disadvantage, denied rights as workers, as women, and, increasingly, as citizens, due to their legal status deviating from the male standard employment relationship. A reading of labor law provisions found devaluation or differently valued labor responsibilities assigned to care and domestic work. US labor standards law treats care work as unskilled, and some aspects of labor activity as non-work. Even more so, the hard to quantify nature of responsibilities and erratic work schedules entailed in the delivery of care leaves care workers in a legal limbo, partly fulfilling the criteria for some workers’ rights and partly excluded from others.
Transnational care work further complicates the claiming of rights because of the type of work performed and because migrant workers cross various jurisdictional boundaries; for example, many of the conventions on human rights circulate at the transnational scale though enforcement occurs primarily at the national and sub-national scales. Paid domestic work, whether performed by migrant or local workers, lacks sufficient regulatory social protections, leaving women who dominate in this form of labor vulnerable to sexual exploitation, long unregulated hours of work, and low wages. Migrant workers face the added problem of claiming rights due to combined disadvantages related to their citizenship and employment status. Furthermore, migrant women, and men, are deprived of the ability to nurture members of their own families, in part due to labor regulations, such as those that grant special work visas only to individual workers. Thinking beyond the boundaries of the nation-state highlights the stakes for women workers on both sides of the citizenship divide. It raises questions about the realization of economic and political rights, and responsibilities for care organized along global care chains: Should rights and protections be limited to those formally recognized as citizens or to all “those territorially present workers? What obligations (responsibilities) do we owe to people whose opportunities for decent work in their own societies have been thwarted, in part, by a system of international political economy that has served to benefit our own nations [including the transfer of care]?” ([
28], p. 141). Can multi-scalar governance assume responsibilities for adjudicating jurisdictional conundrums in order to guarantee women their rights as workers? How can we rationalize the experience of workers under multiple jurisdictions with inconsistent and, at times, contradictory provisions?
Similarly, the analysis of the EU and the ILO directives and conventions on part-time employment found that while extending the principle of equal treatment between standard and nonstandard employment may improve women’s employment conditions, they have not significantly altered the gendered character of these employment forms. On the one hand, these regulations diminish the disadvantages associated with part-time employment by requiring pro rata equality in wages and social benefits, and thereby, promote women’s rights as workers. On the other hand, in law and in practice women in part-time employment continue to suffer disadvantages because neither adequately changes the economic, social and cultural circumstances that contribute to the persistence and growth of “involuntary” part-time employment among women. Consequently, strengthening equal employment opportunities law will not necessarily realize substantive gender equality. Gender inequality will persist as long as the basis for equal treatment refers back to some golden age of industrial or company citizenship based on a standard male work biography reflecting continuous and relatively stable employment unburdened by care responsibilities. For example, though rights to shared parenting responsibilities have entered policy and case law (see [
34]), maternalism still dominates special provisions for care. As Vosko [
37] suggests, policies and labor laws must apply a broader conception of “labor market membership” to acknowledge that “workers typically have gaps in employment, fluctuating levels of employment intensity, and jobs of varying duration over the life-course”. A life-course perspective to labor market membership can connect the gender division of labor responsibilities in households and employment structures into the design of laws aimed at economic security. The increasing trend toward nonstandard and informalized employment poses new challenges for labor laws and labor politics based on a male breadwinner standard employment relationship. A new frame of reference is necessary, one that takes into account shared responsibilities for care.
Who will take responsibility for care and under what conditions will depend on the outcome of future political negotiations, economic pressures, and possibly the recognition of substantive benefits—to both workplace and home—of creating and implementing policies that facilitate share responsibilities for caring and balanced with employment. Acker ([
42], p. 36) puts the argument succinctly, “as long as the workplace is organized on the assumption that workers have no other responsibilities, women will carry the responsibility for care”. Currently, as collective bargaining breaks down and more individuals are “freed” to negotiate their own work conditions, the rights to benefits of such individualized arrangements would most likely accrue to single, highly educated women who can best emulate the masculine embodiment of the labor subject, for whom responsibility for care is a non-issue. One reason why the ILO’s decent work campaign does not go far enough, even rhetorically, is that it fails to articulate an integrative agenda for valuing and realizing shared care responsibilities. Taking a page from CEDAW’s provision on care support would go some way in exhorting men to share the responsibility for raising their children with women.
Two political interventions can promote women’s rights alongside workers’ rights. The first entails a proposal for the development of a “reproductive commons” based on an individual’s rights to publically resourced reproductive labor and services [
48]. Such a reproductive commons can engender substantive equality by establishing a public commitment to share responsibility for the provision and the compensation of reproductive services. The reproductive commons is consistent with the UN Working Group’s cutting-edge proposals for “a social protection floor” to provide care services for children and other persons who require care because of disability, sickness or age ( [
47], p. 7). This intervention could serve single mothers and poor families without the resources to secure their livelihoods through extant measures such as parental leave. Sharing responsibilities for care and guaranteeing a right to an equal distribution of care can free women to participate fully in the political life of their communities and to engage fully in rewarding economic activities. A second political strategy calls for a gender audit analogous to the gender government budgeting exercise enacted by feminist economists. A gender audit applies gender mainstreaming principles already in existence. Such a gender audit could interrogate legal categories in order to expose gender biases; identifying jurisdictional conundrums; and leveraging different scales and legal technicalities as resources for political reform and transformation. It would create a ledger for itemizing labor laws in terms of both the derogation of women’s rights, and how shared responsibilities are treated in order to identify areas in need of reform. As I have argued, women’s rights are not only a matter of law and policy. We must move away from a work-centric political project for emancipation and for tipping the scales of justice. Feminist politics must reclaim spaces, both public and private, to forge new modes of belonging and affective communities that can become the basis of claiming rights and sharing responsibilities. Shared responsibilities, like the history of rights, require negotiation over divisions of labor and expansion of the substantive content of economic and gender justice in the context of work and intimate social relationships. Only then can workers’ rights also ensure women’s rights.