Following Hegel’s Sovereign Beast: An Excursus on the Right of Heroes
Abstract
:1. Introduction
above all to explore the “logics” organizing both the submission of the beast [and the living being] to political sovereignty, and an irresistible and overloaded analogy between a beast and a sovereign supposed to share a space of some exteriority with respect to “law” and “right” (outside the law: above the law: origin and foundation of the law) ([1], p. xiii).
2. The Right of Heroes
3. The Two References
Because coercion destroys itself in its concept, it has its real expression [Darstellung] in the fact that coercion is cancelled [aufgehoben] by coercion; it is therefore not only conditionally right but necessary—namely as a second coercion which cancels an initial coercion. The violation of a contract through failure to perform what it stipulates or to fulfill rightful duties towards the family or state, whether by action or by default, is an initial coercion, or at least force, in so far as I withhold or withdraw from another person a property which belongs to him or a service which is due him ([5], p. 120).
Here we see that this right is legitimated by the orientation of the “natural will”. This will is presented as “a force directed against the Idea of freedom” and, thus, the “right of heroes” constitutes a defensive reaction to the “natural will” ([5], pp. 120–121).5 The fact that it is characterized as a response is significant, because as a secondary coercion it is justified. That is to say, it is justified in the sense that it cancels [aufgehoben] the primary coercion and thus objectively actualizes right. This point is elaborated on in the addition to §93:Pedagogical coercion, or coercion directed against savagery and barbarism [Wildheit und Rohheit], admittedly looks like a primary coercion rather than one which comes after a primary coercion which has already occurred. But the merely natural will is in itself a force directed against the Idea of freedom as that which has being in itself, which must be protected against this uncivilized [ungebildeten] will and given recognition within it. Either an ethical existence [Dasein] has already been posited in the family or state, in which case the natural condition referred to above is an act of violence against it, or there is nothing other than a state of nature, a state governed entirely by force, in which case the Idea sets up a right of heroes against it ([5], pp. 120–121).
Hegel specifies that this right is limited to a specific context, namely, the absence of civilization and that its legitimacy is grounded in the Idea itself, but what is unique about this particular right, aside from the fact that it initiates the dialectic of objective spirit, is that it requires neither recognition nor proportion. As a result, within the state of nature, the hero seems to possess an unlimited right to arbitrarily employ coercive force against the “natural” or “uncivilized” will of others. Hegel emphasizes this point in §350,Within the state, heroes are no longer possible: they occur only in the absence of civilization. The end they pursue is rightful, necessary, and political, and they put it into effect as a cause [Sache] of their own. The heroes who founded states and introduced marriage and agriculture admittedly did not do this as their recognized right, and these actions appear as [a product of] their particular will. But as the higher right of the Idea against the state of nature, this coercion employed by heroes is a rightful coercion, for goodness alone can have little effect when confronted with the force of nature ([5], pp. 120–121).
It is the absolute right of the Idea to make its appearance in legal determinations and objective institutions, beginning with marriage and agriculture, whether the form in which it is actualized appears as divine legislation of a beneficial kind, or as violence [Gewalt] and wrong. This right is the right of heroes to establish states ([5], p. 376).
4. Heroes, Savages and History
Here we see that virtue has its place and actuality in, and only in, a genuine collision of ethical duties. The frequency of these instances directly corresponds to the level of ethical development that the system has achieved. The more developed an ethical order is, the less frequent these collisions are. They belong to those moments that are outside, before, or above history and law. That is to say, they occur within the state of nature. While this adds some clarity to the general role that virtue serves within Hegel’s account of historical development, it does not tell us how the hero acquires this virtue. After all, in the state of nature, individuals have no recourse to an ethical system to guide their actions. Right can only be actualized by an individual that displays “virtue”––a “hero”––but how can virtue be known within the moment? How does one act virtuously in the Hegelian sense? Is it an acquired skill or an innate attribute? This is a very specific question because in order to act virtuously the individual must effectively actualize right, and thus the action in question must serve to further the realization of the Idea. In the Philosophy of Right Hegel describes virtue as being dependent upon “individual discretion” and the “distinctive natural genius of individuals,” but what exactly does this mean ([5], pp. 193–194)? In order to clarify the relationship between the hero and the Idea we must turn to Hegel’s introduction to the Philosophy of History.Within a given ethical order whose relations are fully developed and actualized, virtue in the proper sense has its place and actuality only in extraordinary circumstances, or where the above relations come into collision. But such collisions must be genuine ones, for moral reflection can invent collisions for itself whenever it likes and so give itself a consciousness that something special [Besonderem] is involved and that sacrifices have been made. This is why the form of virtue as such appears more frequently in uncivilized societies and communities, for in such cases, the ethical and its actualization depend more on individual discretion and on the distinctive natural genius of individuals. In this way, the ancients ascribed virtue to Hercules in particular. And since, in the states of antiquity, ethical life had not yet evolved into this free system of self-sufficient development and objectivity, this deficiency had to be made good by the distinctive genius of individuals.—If the theory [Lehre] of virtues is not just a theory of duties and thus includes particular aspects of character which are determined by nature, it will therefore be a natural history of spirit ([5], pp. 193–194).
…for they draw their inspiration from another source, from that hidden spirit whose hour is near but which still lies beneath the surface and seeks to break out without yet having attained an existence in the present. For this spirit, the present world is but a shell which contains the wrong kind of kernel ([2], p. 83).
While the ends of all individual agents, as “knowing and thinking beings”, are “interwoven” with those of the universal the ends of heroes are distinct ([2], p. 81). This distinction is due to the degree to which the hero’s particular ends are “interwoven” with those of the Idea. Typically, individuals rationally pursue their particular ends and are not aware that their actions take part in the mediation of the Idea. Heroes are the exception to this norm. They are those “world historical individuals” that have an “inner vision” of what is necessary in their age, they are “the most far-sighted ones among their contemporaries…and whatever they do is right” ([2], pp. 83–84).The only true ends are those whose content has been produced by the absolute power of the inner spirit itself in the course of its development; and world-historical individuals are those who have willed and accomplished not just the ends of their own imagination or personal opinions, but only those that were appropriate and necessary. Such individuals know what is necessary and timely, and have an inner vision of what it is ([2], p. 83).
The hero can thus be thought of as a vector, a delivery mechanism for the Idea. He is consumed by the Idea and he serves its will with an almost animalistic enthusiasm. Now if we compare the hero to the typical individual, who relates to the Idea through its capacity to rationalize, the hero exists as an inversion, that is, his connection to the Idea is passionate almost to the extent of being animalistic, which is to say, instinctual or unreflective. Consequently, the ends that the hero pursues are not, strictly speaking, his own; he exists as the instrument of right. This is not to say the hero is totally indistinguishable from right. He is an individual subject and, as such, he has an existence distinct from that of the Idea. For Hegel this existence is inessential or contingent,In such individuals, then, that which is necessary in and for itself assumes the form of passion. Great men of this kind admittedly do seem to follow only the dictates of their passions and of their own free will, but the object of their will is universal, and it is this which constitutes their pathos. Passion is simply the energy of their ego, and without this, they could not have accomplished anything. In this respect, the aim of passion and that of the Idea are one and the same; passion is the absolute unity of individual character and the universal. The way in which the spirit in its subjective individuality here coincides exactly with the Idea has an almost animal quality about it ([2], p. 86).
What is interesting here is the relationship between the composite structure of the hero and his actions. For Hegel, there is no relation and even if there were some form of cross contamination—some subjective interruption—this excess would simply be subsumed within the dialectical folding of the system. It would be carried over from one stage only to be rounded off in the next. This rather puzzling structure leaves us with more questions than answers.6Their actions are their entire being, and their whole nature and character are determined by their ruling passion. When their end is attained, they fall aside like empty husks ([2], p. 85).
The qualification is important because if the modifications that originate from the foundations of the state affected the substantial content then the rationality of the actual becomes tainted by the vengeance of heroes. That is, this necessary violation of the law—and we must remember that even for Hegel this is vengeance and not punishment—would not be contained within the pre-history of the state. Consequently it would contaminate and compromise the integrity of the law and with it all of ethical life. Hegel is emphatic on this point,The proper beginning and original foundation of states has rightly been equated with the introduction of agriculture and of marriage…In the consciousness of the ancients, the introduction of agriculture and of the institutions associated with it were divine acts, and they were accordingly treated with religious veneration. A further consequence, which also occurs in the other estates [this quote is referring to the substantial or immediate estate], is that the substantial character of this estate entails modifications with regard to civil law—especially to the administration of justice—and likewise with regard to education and instruction and also to religion; these modifications do not affect the substantial content, but only its form and the development of reflection ([5], pp. 235–236).
Again we see Hegel arguing that the manner or form in which law is founded and by which it develops has no effect on its rational basis. In part, this is because the rationality and necessity of the law are ensured by the concept, but this insurance policy is at the very least questionable. This hard and fast distinction between form and content holds within it an implicit argument. Namely, that form is simultaneously a neutral and insufficient means of conveyance for content. Paradoxically form—like its many family members within the Hegelian system (i.e., nature, contingency, particularity, etc.)—contains content without containing it, it carries or conveys, it bears the mark, but never the fullness of the meaning.8 The truth of this assertion can never be maintained in any particular moment precisely because a moment in isolation is incomplete. It can only be demonstrated as a kind of governing sequence, which can only be verified from the position of absolute knowledge.The historical origin of judge and lawcourts may have taken the form of a patriarchal relationship, of coercion [Gewalt], or of free choice; but this is irrelevant as far as the concept of the thing [Sache] is concerned. To regard the introduction of jurisdiction by sovereign princes and governments as merely a matter [Sache] of arbitrary grace and favour, as Herr von Hailer does [in his Restoration of Political Science], is an example of that thoughtlessness which fails to realize that, since legal and political institutions in general are rational in character, they are necessary in and for themselves, and that the form in which they first arose and were introduced has no bearing on a discussion of their rational basis ([5], p. 252).
We pause here in order to ask a simple question, specifically, who can make these value determinations? Who can determine between necessity and contingency? It is clear according to Hegel that the philosopher can, but if we question the promise of absolute knowledge, we are left with a series of more or less plausible dialectical explanations for historical events. Hegel continues,Particular interests contend with one another, and some are destroyed in the process. But it is from this very conflict and destruction of particular things that the universal emerges, and it remains unscathed itself. For it is not the universal Idea which enters into opposition, conflict and danger; it keeps itself in the background, untouched and unharmed, and sends forth the particular interests of passion to fight and wear themselves out to in its stead. It is what we may call the cunning of reason that it sets the passions to work in its service, so that the agents by which it gives itself existence must pay the penalty and suffer the loss. For the latter belong to the phenomenal world, of which part is worthless and part is of positive value ([2], p. 89).
Here again, how are we to determine where the inadequacy lies? Perhaps “individuals are sacrificed and abandoned” because our conception of the universal is inadequate in relation to the particular. That is, perhaps the slaughter-bench is not necessary in itself; perhaps it is rendered or read as necessary by and for the philosopher. After all, if objective spirit is not the realm of the cross, the philosopher cannot “recognize reason as the rose in the cross of the present” and begin his dance ([5], p. 22). Returning to the quote,The particular is as a rule inadequate in relation to the universal, and individuals are sacrificed and abandoned as a result ([2], p. 89).
The problem here is that the cunning seems to be more of a convenience. That is, the conceptual necessity for the hero is clear, but the rationality, or even plausibility, of his actuality is very limited. He arrives on the stage without explanation and once there he is still not really there. He shares their finitude, their passionate excesses, but he remains distant. He sees beyond them, perhaps even through them. He is outside of their happiness, at one and the same time driven by an unconscious (even animalistic) desire for right. His actions are acts of vengeance. These acts are not motivated by a desire for recognition nor can they be construed as punitive as they lack any sense of proportionality. And yet this force without measure—which impresses its commands into the consciousness of the uncivilized with such force that it takes the form of divine acts—does not contaminate the substantial content that it produces. Hegel maintains that the means that were employed to realize these institutions are irrelevant. They are conceptually necessary and thus justified. The development of the state continues on unabated by the violence that establishes its foundations.The Idea pays the tribute which existence and the transient world exact, but it pays it through the passions of individuals rather than out of its own resources. Caesar had to do what was necessary to overthrow the decaying freedom of Rome; he himself met his end in the struggle, but necessity triumphed: in relation to the Idea, freedom was subordinate to the external events ([2], p. 89).
5. The Philosopher and His Hero
5.1. How Does History Begin?
[A] The State of Nature: In the representational [Vorstellung] thought of Christianity this moment referred to as original sin, but philosophically interpreted it is the primary mode of cognition and it forms the necessary beginning of all consciousness. In this mode of cognition the subject is driven by natural, object-directed desire. It does not recognize its separation from the natural world and because it does not recognize this separation it cannot develop. Seeing as “spirit is to be free and is to be what it is through itself” and that “nature is, for man, only the starting point that he ought to transform” this mode of cognition constitutes an act of violence against the Idea ([16], p. 63). In response the Idea establishes the ‘right of heroes’ ([5], p. 120). At this stage ‘man’ is an unfertile seed.[B] The Hero: This character also arrives out of conceptual necessity, which is to say, he does not develop dialectically within a given moment or shape. He can be thought of as the materialization of “the divine principle of turning” in that he initiates or makes possible the “return to self” by “giving the wound” ([17], p. 103). He enacts heroic vengeance on the uncivilized and thereby exposes the emptiness of the initial mode of cognition as the executor, or translator of the Idea. He fertilizes the seed.
5.2. Does the State of Nature End?
5.3. What are the Implications of a Continually Recurring State of Nature?
Each is engaged in a process of re-writing: Hegel rewrites God, Menard rewrites Don Quixote; yet what they aim to produce is not a copy, but the truth that the original had failed to fully grasp. Each struggles with a task that is, at least to them, simple: it is after all blatantly evident to the trained eye, and yet it is, at least for the time being, ineffable. Once again Menard captures the essence of their struggle,My purpose is merely astonishing…the final term of a theological or metaphysical proof—the world around us, or God, or chance, or universal Forms—is no more final, no more uncommon, than my revealed novel. The sole difference is that philosophers publish pleasant volumes containing the intermediate stages of their work, while I am resolved to suppress those stages of my own ([18], p. 91).
Hegel, as the philosopher, must prove his theory by translating actuality into the text. Yet, as a translator, his work does not belong to the moment. He always arrives too late; he always arrives in the wake of the author. He reads what has been already written and copies it into his book of life. Yet, if we were to ask him who taught him how to read, he would be unable to answer. Perhaps, he is a sign of the end, a product of the penultimate moment, but seeing as he is bound within that moment he is unable to answer us in any definitive way. He does not belong to the now of the moment. He is a stranger to the life of the living. He strives to “forget himself” in order to be able to serve the “truth” of Spirit ([7], p. 45). As such, all that he can tell us is that he was chosen by the Absolute, that he is conceptually necessary, a product of Spirit’s gathering strength. Much like his hero, he simply arrives. And much like his hero, he accomplishes the impossible: he gathers meaning from death. Only the dead can enter his book. Only the dead can be born again in spirit. Only they can be absolved. The living can only share in the “living feeling” (auto-affection) of absolution by facing death ([19], pp. 250–251).The task I have undertaken is not in essence difficult…If I could just be immortal, I could do it ([18], pp. 91–92).
5.4. Can We Think of Objective Spirit as a Process of Writing?
If we accept this interpretation and read the Philosophy of Right as an allegory then we must also address the question of authorship. That is, if the text is an allegory, if the meaning of the text is concealed behind the explicit figures, then who is writing? According to Hegel the author is the Absolute. His philosophy is merely the interpretative apparatus: the reading machine. As Marx observes, the subjects are “reduced to…names of the Idea,” and as names or components they all work to realize the auto-affective desire of the Absolute ([20], p. 67). History is thus always already an allegory written by proxy, yet there are moments when the text goes beyond the limits of allegory and indeed of writing itself. The moment we have selected in this essay is such a moment. In this moment, meaning does not enter the text allegorically—hidden or obscured by a façade—but, directly. The death of the uncivilized occurs as a writing-out of the other. This act of writing-out explodes [within] the text,As the whole point of the exercise is to create an allegory to confer on some empirically existent thing or other the significance of the realized Idea, it is obvious that these vessels will have fulfilled their function as soon as they have become a determinate incarnation of a moment of the life of the Idea. Hence, the universal appears everywhere as a determinate particular, while the individual never achieves its true universality ([20], p. 99).
Heroic vengeance enters the text as a leap out of the text. It enters as what cannot be contained, as a flash, an instant of “unheard, inaudible, deafening speech” ([22], p. 331). The text recoups, it recovers after the instant has passed, finds marriage and agriculture already in place and continues on. The text continues on,As nature enters that form, so it remains in it, just as a shell starts suddenly towards its zenith and then rests for a moment in it; metal, when heated, does not turn soft like wax, but all at once becomes liquid and remains so—for this phenomenon is the transition into the absolute opposite and so is infinite, and this emergence of the opposite out of infinity or out of its nothingness is a leap. The shape, in its new-born strength, at first exists for itself alone, before it becomes conscious of its relation to another. Just so, the growing individuality has both the delight of the leap in entering a new form and also an enduring pleasure in its new form, until it gradually opens up to the negative, and in its decline too it is sudden and brittle ([21], p. 132; see [3], pp. 106–107].
In the instant of vengeance—the instant that cannot be written—a sacrifice occurs and through it “life” is “purified of the negative,” but, this “purification” or “living feeling” of the self as it is in itself (auto-affection) can only become complete by stepping through (and thus beyond) determination. The text that remains is thus driven to what it can only interpret as autophagy. It consumes itself. It eats itself in order to feel itself. It cannot see the remain(s). It casts them aside as inessential contingencies or simply evidence of the insufficiency of the finite: the insufficiency of the “word” itself. Hegel’s text is a text is written by and through the sacrifice of the word made flesh, but in order to maintain the purity of this or indeed these (the sacrifices occur in the plural) sacrifices it must––and can never––extend beyond simply writing “death” to an absolute writing-out. Hegel’s text must—and cannot—finish its meal. What is left is an endless feast in which “the work of the ‘No’ in its multiple forms behind which reading, and writing, prepare for the advent of a ‘Yes’ both unique and ever reiterated in the circularity where there is no longer any first and last affirmation” ([9], p. 73). What is left is a choice. We can rejoin the feast and follow the dialectic circle towards a future that only ever sees itself coming.10 Or, we can hold off. We can take a step back from the table and the endless clinking of glasses, the endless refrain of “salute” and “adieu.” We can begin to ask precisely what––and who––we are saying good-bye to.At the same time, in the manner presented above, this life fends off involvement with the negative—for [since what we have so far called positive has in the event turned out to be the negative considered in itself] it confronts the negative as objective and fate, and by consciously conceding to the negative a power and a realm, at the sacrifice of a part of itself, it maintains its own life purified of the negative ([21], p. 133).
6. Hegel’s Beasts and Sovereigns
- 1. The title of the seminar in the yearbook for the École des hautes études en sciences sociales (EHESS) clearly marks it as a continuation: “Questions de responsabilité (IX. La bête et le soverain)” ([1], p. xiv).
- 2. Despite the similarities between the “right of heroes” and the struggle for recognition that occurs in the relationship of lordship and servitude (mentioned only once in the Philosophy of Right in §57 and gone over in detail in both the Phenomenology, 178–196 and the Encyclopedia, §430–436), there are distinctions. While both occur prior to the foundation of the State, the descriptions given in both the Philosophy of Right (see, §93, 350; as well as, §70, 150 and in the Encyclopedia §432) and in the Introduction to the Lectures on the Philosophy of World History suggest that the “hero” or “great man” precedes the struggle for recognition ([2], pp. 68–93). The distinction between the hero and the struggle for recognition is quite clear. In the struggle, each is motivated by the desire for the recognition of the other. The master-slave relationship begins with struggle to the death in which one party submits. If one of the two dies the moment fails. The hero does not desire the recognition of the uncivilized. He forces them to submit to his will. The moment does not fail with death of the uncivilized. Rather, their deaths clear the ground for the foundations of the state.
- 3. n Glas, Derrida exposes this pattern of interruption within the logic of identity by tracing the course of the “remain(s)” ([3], p. 252). The place of the “remain(s)” within this pattern is doubled as it is, at one and the same time, the infinitesimal remainder of the active process of dialectics and the limit that provokes its repetition. In effect, the “remain(s)” persist within Hegel’s text as both the very possibility of dialectics and a perpetual contestation of both the scope and the stakes of “absolute knowledge.” As such, the affinity between the “remain(s)” and différance becomes clear as both make “it possible to translate Hegel at that particular point—which is also absolutely decisive point in his discourse—without further notes or specifications” ([4], p. 14). The translation that these quasi-transcendental concepts makes possible is the translation of an unacknowledged limit within Hegel’s text. This limit bears with it an ethical question that Hegel’s “three-stroke engine” is designed to resolve. And yet, as Derrida notes, “a sensible remain(s) prevents the three-stroke engine from turning over or running smoothly…the remain(s) does nothing but promise a new anniversary” ([3], p. 252). As such, each moment within “objective spirit” is both structured and carried forward by the promise of right without “remain(s),” that is, a right beyond the shadow of doubt, a “reconciliation” that would enable us to “delight in the present,” but this delight has a price. For each speculative “rose,” there must be another objective “cross” ([5], p. 22). The necessity of the cross would of course not be comprehended from within the moment—Hegel clearly articulates that “objective spirit” is incomplete, and while this incompleteness can and must be suppressed and constrained by the state, it can only achieve “reconciliation” in “absolute spirit”—but, from the perspective of the philosopher. As such, the question of the “remain(s)”—which is to say, the “particular point” within the text that différance translates—contests the judgment of the philosopher in a way that Hegel’s text cannot anticipate ([6], pp. 253–254).
- 4. Despite its necessity, Hegel formally excludes this moment from the Philosophy of Right in §2. But, the rationale that is given for the exclusion of the “starting point” or “coming into being” of right is, in a word, unconvincing. To argue that the “determinate starting point” of right should be excluded from this text because it is the product of the proof that precedes it is, at best, an appeal to formalism (which, ironically, was an accusation that Hegel was very fond of using against Kant). On these grounds, we could perhaps excuse Hegel from including the full proof (in that it pertains to the concept as it is “in itself” and thus falls within the purview of the Logic), but to simply argue that both the proof and the result are outside of the science of right is arbitrary. This initial moment directly pertains to the “concept of right and its actualization,” and so cannot be outside the text ([5], p. 25). Nor can Hegel not argue that the logical proof is identical to its “coming into being.” If this was the case, then there is no need for the dialectic of objective spirit and everything would be contained within the ontological dialectic of absolute spirit. So, why is the “product” excluded in this instance? Hegel attempts to justify this exclusion in the addition to §2 by appealing to the dialectical dynamics of the system. In effect, he is simply arguing that any contingency that may result from this missing “starting point” will be rounded off as the concept is objectively realized, or more simply, the end justifies the means. As a transitional confrontation between the concept and nature, it must involve some degree of contingency, some collateral damage, and, contrary to Hegel’s assertion, this belongs within the science of right. Hegel tacitly concedes this by referring to this excluded beginning to support arguments that he presents within the text (see [5], pp. 51, 86–88, 120–121, 130, 193–194, 207–209, 224–225, 230–231, 235–236, 243, 250, 375–376]. When closely examined, these references—in combination with the corresponding logical “proofs”—present us with a partial image of the very moment that Hegel explicitly excludes from the text.
- 5. Hegel’s characterization of the “natural will” is reflected in his interpretation of both original sin and the state of nature. In the Philosophy of Right this characterization can be found in §18 and the addition to §139. This provides us with Hegel’s general rationale for dismissing much of the content of the myth of the fall, but it provides no specific details and thus it should also be compared to his more extended interpretations, which occur in the addition to §24 of the Encyclopaedia Logic and in the Lectures on the Philosophy of Religion (see [10], pp. 104–108, 207–211, 300–304). We should also note that Hegel’s reading of the doctrine of original sin is far from orthodox. This becomes evident when we consider the number of divergences that his reading contains:1. Man is not created innocent.2. Sin is not the result of a decision. Nor is it prompted by an external actor.3. The expulsion is not a punishment. It is an awakening to an ontological reality.4. Shame is not the product of guilt, but of the awareness of the ontological condition of man.For a more detailed account of Hegel’s interpretation of the Fall and of his relationship to theology, refer to Cyril O’Reagan’s The Heterodox Hegel; and for a consideration of its place within the Philosophy of Right, refer to Adriaan Peperzak’s indispensible Modern Freedom: Hegel’s Legal, Moral, and Political Philosophy.
- 6. Other commentators have also found Hegel’s account of the “world historical individual” puzzling. Eric Weil touches upon this issue in his Hegel and the State and Ido Geiger produces a unique reading of the hero in relation to Antigone and war in his The Founding Act of Modern Ethical Life. Geiger’s account raises a series of very interesting questions, but it does not take into account the distinctions that divide the Phenomenology and the Philosophy of Right on this point. For instance, Antigone’s claim pertains directly to the family and recognition whereas the hero’s in the Philosophy of Right precede both the family and recognition. Nonetheless, Geiger produces an innovative and intriguing interpretation. In Hegel’s Theory of the Modern State, Avineri argues that Hegel’s account is contradictory as it seems that, at times, the individual is conscious of its ends, and at others, semi- to totally unconscious ([11], p. 233). Taylor claims that Avineri’s observations are invalid due to the apocryphal nature of his source (i.e., Reason in History). But, simply disqualifying a text on the basis of canonical accord, and then reconciling the text on the basis of a historical perspective, renders the argument unconvincing. After all, it is Hegel’s account of the “world historical individual” and the so-called cunning of reason that enables his system to introduce the ontological assertion from the greater Logic—which Taylor openly objects to—into history and effectively determine the content of “unconscious motivation” and render it totally conscious ([12], pp. 237–238). The hero highlights the troubling circularity of Hegel’s ontological claim. In that, the identity of the hero can only be secured from the position of absolute knowledge and absolute knowledge can only come to be if its very possibility is built into being. In short, the philosopher guarantees the truth of the “seed,” and the “seed” is the very possibility of the philosopher. As Hyppolite notes, the problem here is the very historicity of absolute knowledge ([13], p. 36).
- 7. I add the image of the bell and its sounding [klang] to invoke both Derrida’s work in Glas and the sounding out that formally ends the “dull innocence” of the flower religions and begins the “earnestness of warring life” and “guilt” that is characteristic of the so-called animal religions ([3], p. 4; [7], p. 420).
- 8. This distinction (i.e., form and content, nature and spirit, etc.) is maintained in Hegel’s account of cognition and signification:The distinction between thought and will is simply that between theoretical and practical attitudes. But they are not two separate faculties on the contrary the will is a particular way of thinking—thinking translating itself into existence [Dasein], thinking as the drive to give itself existence. This distinction between thought and will can be expressed as follows. When I think of an object [Gegenstand], I make it into a thought and deprive it of its sensuous quality; I make it into something which is essentially and immediately mine. For it is only when I think that I am with myself [bei mir], and it is only by comprehending it that I can penetrate an object; it then no longer stands opposed to me, and I have deprived it of that quality of its own which it had for itself in opposition to me. Just as Adam says to Eve: ‘You are flesh of my flesh and bone of my bone’, so does spirit say: ‘This is spirit of my spirit, and alien character has disappeared’ ([5], p. 35).This ‘disappearance’ within cognition is compelling. The fact that it has disappeared entails that there was a previous appearance. Of course Hegel will dismiss this appearance as merely superficial, merely form, yet how does it disappear? Does it simply vanish without a trace or could it remain within the system? Could it be that cognition accumulates disappearances? This process of cognition, that is, of cognition as translation and disappearance, is precisely where Derrida’s reading disrupts Hegel’s text. Derrida effectively interrogates Hegel’s text by tracing the repetition of disappearance within Hegel’s semiology (see [14]) and his account of love and the family in “ethical life” (see [3]).
- 10. A mode of futurity that it shares with the Oroborous—that miraculous creature that is always open to receiving whatever may appear over the horizon, but in the practice of its openness it finds that once it has sunk its teeth into what initially appeared to it as another, it encounters only itself.
References
- Derrida, J. The Beast and the Sovereign; Bennington, G., Translator; University of Chicago Press: Chicago, IL, USA, 2009; Volume 1. [Google Scholar]
- Hegel, G.W.F. Lectures on the Philosophy of World History: Introduction; Nisbet, H.B., Translator; Cambridge University Press: New York, NY, USA, 1980. [Google Scholar]
- Derrida, J. Glas; Leavey, J.P., Jr.; Rand, R., Translators; University of Nebraska Press: Lincoln, NB, USA, 1990. [Google Scholar]
- Derrida, J. Différance. In Margins of Philosophy; Bass, A., Translator; University of Chicago Press: Chicago, IL, USA, 1984. [Google Scholar]
- Hegel, G.W.F. Elements of the Philosophy of Right; Wood, A.W., Ed.; Nisbet, H.B., Translator; Cambridge University Press: New York, NY, USA, 2004. [Google Scholar]
- Hegel, G.W.F. Philosophy of Mind; Wallace, W., Translator; Oxford University Press: New York, NY, USA, 1978. [Google Scholar]
- Hegel, G.W.F. Phenomenology of Spirit; Miller, A.V., Translator; Oxford University Press: New York, NY, USA, 1977. [Google Scholar]
- Derrida, J. A time for farewells: Heidegger [read by] Hegel [read by] Malabou. In The Future of Hegel: Plasticity, Temporality and Dialectic; During, L., Translator; Routledge: New York, NY, USA, 2005. [Google Scholar]
- Blanchot, M. The Writing of the Disaster; Smock, A., Translator; University of Nebraska Press: Lincoln, NB, USA, 1995. [Google Scholar]
- Hegel, G.W.F. Lectures on the Philosophy of Religion; Hodgson, P.C., Ed.; Oxford University Press: New York, NY, USA, 2007; Volume 3. [Google Scholar]
- Avineri, S. Hegel’s Theory of the Modern State; Cambridge University Press: New York, NY, USA, 1972. [Google Scholar]
- Taylor, C. Hegel; Cambridge University Press: New York, NY, USA, 2005. [Google Scholar]
- Hyppolite, J. Logic and Existence; Lawlor, L.; Sen, A., Translators; SUNY Press: Albany, NY, USA, 1997. [Google Scholar]
- Derrida, J. The Pit and the Pyramid: Introduction to Hegel’s Semiology. In Margins of Philosophy; Bass, A., Translator; University of Chicago Press: Chicago, IL, USA, 1982. [Google Scholar]
- Hamacher, W. Pleroma: Reading in Hegel; Walker, N.; Jarvis, S., Translators; Stanford University Press: Stanford, CA, USA, 1998. [Google Scholar]
- Hegel, G.W.F. The Encyclopaedia Logic; Geraets, T.F.; Suchting, W.A.; Harris, H.S., Translators; Hackett Publishing: Indianapolis, IN, USA, 1991. [Google Scholar]
- Hegel, G.W.F. Lectures on the Philosophy of Religion; Hodgson, P.C., Ed.; Hodgson, P.C., Translator; Oxford University Press: New York, NY, USA, 2007; Volume 1. [Google Scholar]
- Borges, J.L. Pierre Menard, Author of the Quixote. In Collected Fictions; Hurley, A., Translator; Penguin Press: New York, NY, USA, 1998. [Google Scholar]
- Hegel, G.W.F. Early Theological Writings; Knox, T.M., Translator; University of Pennsylvania Press: Philadelphia, PA, USA, 1996. [Google Scholar]
- Marx, K. Critique of Hegel’s Doctrine of the State. In Early Writings; Livingstone, R.; Benton, G., Translators; Penguin Books: New York, NY, USA, 1992. [Google Scholar]
- Hegel, G.W.F. Natural Law; Knox, T.M., Translator; University of Pennsylvania Press: Phildelphia, PA, USA, 1975. [Google Scholar]
- Nancy, J.L. Exscription. In The Birth to Presence; Hamacher, W., Ed.; Caws, M.; Caws, P.; Holmes, B.; Harrison, T.; King, N.; Laennec, C.; Lydon, K.; Moddel, P.; McVarish, E.; Sartiliot, C.; Syrotinski, M.; Trumble, R.; Wellbery, D., Translators; Stanford University Press: Stanford, CA, USA, 1993. [Google Scholar]
- Bataille, G. Guilty; Kendall, S., Translator; SUNY Press: Albany, NY, USA, 2011. [Google Scholar]
© 2013 by the authors; licensee MDPI, Basel, Switzerland. This article is an open-access article distributed under the terms and conditions of the Creative Commons Attribution license (http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/3.0/).
Share and Cite
Nichols, J.B.D. Following Hegel’s Sovereign Beast: An Excursus on the Right of Heroes. Societies 2013, 3, 24-42. https://doi.org/10.3390/soc3010024
Nichols JBD. Following Hegel’s Sovereign Beast: An Excursus on the Right of Heroes. Societies. 2013; 3(1):24-42. https://doi.org/10.3390/soc3010024
Chicago/Turabian StyleNichols, Joshua Ben David. 2013. "Following Hegel’s Sovereign Beast: An Excursus on the Right of Heroes" Societies 3, no. 1: 24-42. https://doi.org/10.3390/soc3010024
APA StyleNichols, J. B. D. (2013). Following Hegel’s Sovereign Beast: An Excursus on the Right of Heroes. Societies, 3(1), 24-42. https://doi.org/10.3390/soc3010024