1. Introduction
Entropy Theory can be compared to several other interdisciplinary mathematical theories that involve numerical representations of ordered structures (see, e.g., [
1]). In particular, an appealing similarity arises between the utility representation problem in Economics and the search for entropy functions in Thermodynamics. This has been analyzed by paying attention to different aspects of the kind of representability that could be encountered (see [
2,
3,
4,
5,
6,
7,
8,
9,
10,
11]). Apart from Utility Theory in Economics, other theories, e.g., Measurement Theory in Psychology and Cognitive Sciences (see [
12,
13]), Shannon Entropy in Computation [
14]) and Finance (see [
15,
16]), or Fuzzy Set Theory (see [
17]), give rise to quite similar problems. Basically, we may say that all of them try to implement some ad hoc method or construct a suitable tool to convert qualitative scales into quantitative or numerical ones.
This is the clue.
Thus, in the case of Utility Theory in Economics, the device would be the concept of a numerical representation or utility function, whereas, in the case of Entropy Theory in Thermodynamics, the tool will be the notion of an entropy function. These theories share a common mathematical background.
Just to put an appealing example of a manuscript that analyzes the theoretical grounds of Entropy Theory in Thermodynamics, we choose an interesting paper by Cooper (see [
18]). We have selected that paper by Cooper ([
18]), dated 1967, because it shows a clear formulation to compare axiomatic Thermodynamics to representability theory of ordered structures in Mathematics. Indeed, it was published in the Journal of Mathematical Analysis and Applications, as an attempt to bring closer physical notions arising in Thermodynamics to pure mathematicians, by means of a rigorous mathematical setting. Needless to say, we are indeed aware that other (much more modern) axiomatic approaches to the concept of entropy have arisen in Physics. For instance, in an excellent survey by Lieb and Yngvason [
19] (dated 1999), an axiomatic foundation of the second law of thermodynamics that includes the construction of entropy can be achieved in a more physical way. This approach is, in some sense, more general than Cooper’s one in [
18], in that it does not require the concept of empirical temperature. Nevertheless, and we insist in this key fact that, from the point of view of mathematicians, those physical approaches have exactly the same mathematical treatment, namely the use of representability theory of ordered structures to convert qualitative scales into quantitative ones. The new quantitative scales are defined through some entropy function in the physical setting. Thus, in the aim of building bridges, we have decided to follow Cooper’s ideas, since, in our opinion, his presentation is perhaps more didactical, despite more modern approaches having appeared in Physics in the last fifty years.) In that key work, the author studies the foundations of Thermodynamics and the existence of entropy functions on state spaces of thermodynamic systems. Three different formulations of the second law of Thermodynamics from to Clausius, Kelvin and Carathéodory (see, e.g., [
20,
21]) are considered and it is proven that the satisfaction of Carathéodory’s axioms (see, e.g., [
22,
23]) is not sufficient for the existence of an entropy function even in simple spaces. Cooper studies this problem by formulating a concept of an accessibility relation ⇝ on the state space (also known as the phase system)
of a thermodynamical system. That relation on
is a total preorder, and an entropy function is defined to be a real-valued function on
that preserves ⇝.
Even if we can mathematically justify the existence of an entropy function, a new problem appears, namely, the construction of a suitable one. To prove the existence and to describe a construction are horses of a different color. In this sense, it could be reasonable to compare how mathematicians and, say, physicists, argue even when the theories they are studying have the same mathematical roots. To simplify greatly, we may say that sometimes the physicist has at hand the result of an experiment or else the evidence of a real-life phenomenon, so that she/he wants to mathematically justify what happens and why. In this situation, the starting point is, so-to-say, that experiment or evidence, and Mathematics acts just as a theoretical support to conclude that everything is in good order. People who research in abstract pure mathematics, however, almost always start from an abstract system of axioms to build a theory, and nothing more. Everything should be obtained from the axioms, and even real-life evidence and situations should appear as “particular cases” of the corresponding theory that emanates from the axiomatic system involved. These two ways of thinking have, obviously, many points in common. However, they also have intrinsic differences (for a nice discussion about how mathematicians vs. physicists argue, see, e.g., [
24]). A clear example of the above discussion appears when studying entropies. Most of the classical definitions of an entropy arising in Thermodynamics use some sort of path-integral. In Mathematics, however, if starting from a purely abstract point of view we deal with a totally ordered set satisfying some technical conditions that warrant the existence of a numerical representation (also known as order-isotony or utility function), the fact of that representation being done through a path-integral is quite difficult and unintuitive. In a mathematical abstract setting, only in very special cases the construction of a suitable integral that represents the ordered structure can be done in a small number of steps.
Therefore, it seems necessary here to make a discussion about the theoretical existence of a representation (e.g., an entropy) and its practical construction.
These problems, certainly related and complementary, are of a very different nature.
By the way, Boltzmann’s works extended the understanding of thermodynamic entropy towards a statistical perspective. Gibbs (see [
25]) brought the notion of grand canonical ensemble concept and introduced statistical entropy in classical continuous systems. Von Neumann then presented the so-called now Von Neumann entropy in quantum systems (see [
26]). In addition, other than development in Physics, Claude Shannon (see [
14]) independently introduced in 1948 an alternative axiomatic approach to justify the form of a concept of entropy related to communication problems in Information Theory. Shannon setting uses three axioms that are actually equivalent to those issued by Carathéodory and Cooper. In fact, E. T. Jaynes’ pioneer works (see [
27]) demonstrated that the forms of thermodynamic, statistical and Von Neumann entropy are actually rooted in the same mathematical bases, namely, they can be stated by using the same three axioms that Shannon used in [
14], and this leads to equivalent forms of entropy, each of them for its corresponding context. Thus, despite having selected Cooper’s approach focusing on axiomatic entropy in Thermodynamics, we could have also alternatively chosen Shannon’s setting in Information Theory (as well as other mathematically equivalent ones) to start with. Furthermore, following Bayesian interpretation of probability theory, Laplace’s insufficient principle and Gibbs’s ensemble treatment, E. T. Jaynes argued that entropy is not only a physical quantity representing scale of order but also a tool for inductive inference. This topic has been investigated in the past decades by several scholars including J. Shore, R. Johnson, J. Skilling, C. Rodríguez, A. Caticha and K.H. Knuth (see, e.g., [
28,
29]), thus leading to a whole new understanding of the meaning of entropy, from interdisciplinary mathematical, physical and philosophical angles. In addition, there exist past related works on axiomatic entropy in the teleparallel alternative of general relativity with a non-minimal coupling between the gravity and scalar field (see, e.g., [
30]). In some of these studies, ordering relations constitute a basis to obtain laws, as we do in the present paper.)
1.1. Contents of the Paper
The present paper constitutes a survey on the main mathematical theories and results that support the concept of an entropy arising in Physics and Chemistry among other neighboring disciplines. Then, a critical discussion is made about how mathematicians have achieved some of the key results, and what could be the scope of such results in entropy theory. A particular attention is paid to the construction of entropy functions. Other possible miscellaneous applications and similar theories are also commented as a by-product.
The schema of the paper goes as follows:
After the Introduction, in
Section 2, we select the key definitions, both on entropies and ordered structures, that are necessary to start with. In
Section 3, we pay attention to the representability of total preorders, as well as to the construction of utility functions (also known as order-isotonies). In
Section 4, we analyze the concepts of mixing and competition, commonly encountered in various entropy settings, in the light of numerical representations of certain ordered structures, that may be defined on a set endowed with some algebraic operation compatible with the ordering, and perhaps some related topology, too. Sometimes, these ideas of looking for entropy functions that preserve some algebraic operation and/or are continuous with respect to some topology, appear directly in a set of axioms, as in [
18] or much more recently in [
19]. However, from the mathematical point of view, the representability theory of algebraic and/or topological structures has special features, and should be analyzed after a well understanding of the representability of, say, total preorders (without any additional structure). To avoid misunderstanding, we warn the reader that, here, the word “topology” or the expression “topological structure” should be understood only in the sense of General Topology (see [
31]) and not in the sense of a “topological configuration of discrete structures” that is typical, for instance, in the study of graphs and networks, where concepts related to entropy, as the so-called “graph entropy”, are also of common use (see, e.g., [
32]).Other expressions, such as “topological sorting” (see, e.g., [
33,
34]) used in graph theory to obtain a suitable linear order on the nodes of a directed acyclic graph, are also disparate from the concept of “topology” throughout the present manuscript. Basically, we work with a topology as the collection of open subsets of a given set. We do this, mainly, to handle continuity of functions.) This is the reason that forces us to study this question in a separate section. Then,
Section 5 is devoted to studying the representability numerical of interval orders and semiorders.
Section 6 analyzes questions relative to intransitivities related to physical or chemical processes. This is made in the light of suitable ordered structures, namely interval orders and semiorders. As far as we know, the use of this kind of orderings in entropy theory in Thermodynamics or Chemistry is new. Interval orders are used to interpret intransitivities (see [
1]), whereas semiorders, that constitute a special case of interval orders, can be used to interpret situations in which two systems cannot be distinguished until they differ in a fixed amount, called threshold or “quantum”. Therefore, the novelty of the use of semiorders is that they constitute a helpful mathematical tool to deal with quantum theories related to entropy. In
Section 7, we pay special attention to the construction of numerical representations.
This study is necessary, in our opinion, because the construction of numerical representations of ordered structures in a pure mathematical abstract setting could seriously differ from the typical understanding of an entropy in Thermodynamics as, say, a physical concept given by a suitable path-independent integral.
Thus, we should explain how representations of orderings can be built in a way so that they are defined by some sort of integral.
The manuscript is closed with a Discussion (
Section 8) and a final
Section 9 of conclusions, open problems and further comments, pointing out several lines of research to complete the panorama.
1.2. Objectives, Methodology and Original Work
We warn the reader that this paper, despite presenting interdisciplinary results, has been conceived as a mathematical one. We think that analyzing the mathematics that appears in the basis of axiomatic theories on entropy could help other people working in several disciplines, perhaps disparate.
It is not our intention to compare one another all the axiomatics that have been introduced in Physics to handle the concept of entropy in quite different settings, mainly in Thermodynamics. Instead, it is our aim to show how the theory of representability of ordered structures is the mathematical cornerstone on which the most typical axiomatics of entropy lean. That is, instead of working at some of the various physical levels or in some concrete physical theory, we go to the background level of pure abstract mathematics.
To do so, we have chosen some particular axiomatics of entropy arising in Physics or Information Theory, namely the one due to Carathéodory issued in 1909 and then improved by many authors such as Cooper, Lieb and Yngvason, or even Shannon, among others. As commented before, we do not think it is effective to compare and analyze each one of the possible axiomatics.
When observing most of these existing systems of axioms, we notice that most of them set a list of postulates that basically establish that the state space is endowed with a binary relation, usually called accessibility, that is a linear order or a total preorder. Then, they look for a real-valued function called entropy that preserves the ordering and is a quantitative scale to compare states. This is done from the axioms, by proving the corresponding existence theorem.
Therefore, most of these axiomatics share the same mathematical background. Thus, it seems crucial to directly analyze that abstract basis, since understanding it well, we could use the subsequent abstract mathematical results that derive from it, namely the fundamentals of the theory of the numerical representability of ordered structures, to support each of those physical theories at least in their axiomatical setting.
Of course, this last step leads to some changes of nomenclature, depending on the concrete theories involved. However, and we insist on this, the mathematical basis is the same.
Bearing this in mind, our objective here is to analyze the order theoretical questions that arise in those axiomatics of entropy. Thus, we develop a rigorous mathematical battery of results that could help us the particular features of each possible interdisciplinary situation.
In those axiomatics we also observe that, from the abstract mathematical point of view, some structures appear there amalgamated. That is, some axioms are of ordinal stuff, some other ones deal with algebraic operations and several others involve continuity, that is a topological concept. All of them appear mixed or combined. Unfortunately, from the point of view of the mathematical theory of numerical representability of ordered structures, this could be confusing and sometimes misleading. Thus, a formal theory should begin by studying the representability of linear orders and total preorders, with no extra structure. Then, new compatible structures can be added as algebraic operations first, and then continuity with respect to some topology. In general, it is much clearer to study these mathematical additional structures separately.
Once the main mathematical results have been obtained, one can come back to the axiomatics of entropy to rewrite or rearrange, if necessary, the set of axioms. Sometimes, some condition should be added ab initio to the state systems because, at least from the mathematical abstract setting, it cannot be taken for granted. For example, if we want to work with connected spaces, or if we want to deal with systems that can interact, we should postulate that in the axioms. In other words, an abstract set is neither given a priori a topology (to deal with connectedness or continuity), nor a sort of algebraic operation (to handle interactions or reactions).
The original work made in this paper can be summarized as follows:
Identify the mathematical background that most axiomatics of entropy share. That basis is the theory of numerical representability of linear orders and total preorders. It is also the basis of several other theories, for instance, Utility Theory in Economics.
Isolate the mathematical components of the axiomatics. In several axiomatics encountered in the literature, the consideration of several mathematical aspects of the phase systems appears as a mixture or list of properties. It is more convenient to analyze each aspect independently, since this also gives us a further idea of the scope of each property considered. Thus, it is mathematically reasonable to study first ordered structures without any additional condition, and then pass to consider algebraic ordered structures and finally continuity as well as other topological features.
Point out that nothing can be taken for granted a priori, if it has not been said in the corresponding axioms, and correct some mistakes arising in classical papers. Any property that is implicitly supposed but not declared could lead to mathematical mistakes as well as flaws in the proofs. This has already happened in [
18,
19], among other sources. Perhaps due to implicitly assuming some properties that have not been declared, some classical results have flaws in the proofs or are based in intuitions that are false in the abstract setting. This happens in [
18,
35,
36,
37] (see also [
2,
3]). Apart from this, other mistakes of different nature arising, e.g., in [
18], have also been corrected.
Suggest new axioms that should be added. This is necessary to obtain correct results and avoid the mistakes that are due either to false intuitions or to the fact of taking some properties for granted.
Identify the theory of numerical representability of interval orders as the key to deal with intransitivities. This fact is well known in the corresponding mathematical literature. However, as far as we know, it is uncommon in the analysis of axiomatics of entropy. Although several recent papers (see, e.g., [
38]) have analyzed in depth intransitivities encountered in various physical or chemical processes, no use of the concept of an interval order as the main tool is observed there, as already commented in [
1].
Show some parallelism among axiomatics of entropy and other interdisciplinary theories. In particular, we point out that several crucial results in the theory of numerical representability of ordered structures were indeed launched in journals devoted to the study of utility theory in Economics.
Use semiorders as the key mathematical concept to deal with intransitivities that are due to the existence of constant thresholds of discrimination. As in the case of interval orders, this seems to be new in the axiomatics of entropy. In the case of quantum theories, it could be crucial in future research to interpreting quanta as a thresholds of comparison, and work in the framework of the numerical representability of semiorders in the sense of Scott and Suppes (see [
39,
40]).
Analyze the construction of numerical representations of orderings, in particular when they are given by integrals. To achieve a theoretical result that states that a numerical representation must exist, because otherwise we arrive to a mathematical contradiction, is quite different from furnishing a construction of a suitable representation. We pay particular attention to the case in which the numerical representations are defined through some sort of integral.
4. Mixing and Competition Related to Entropy
A glance at the classical paper by Cooper [
18] shows us a whole section devoted to the analysis of “composition of systems: additivity of entropy” (see also [
4]). How could we interpret this concept?
The same situation appears in the much more recent survey by Lieb and Yngvasson (see [
19]), namely, they claim that:
For every system there is a function, S, on the space of its (equilibrium) states, with the property that one can go adiabatically from a state X to a state Y if and only if . This, in essence, is the “entropy principle”. The S function can clearly be multiplied by an arbitrary constant and still continue to do its job, and thus it is not at all obvious that the function for system 1 has anything to do with the function for system 2. Again, we should point out that this is an intuition that is in general false, unless we assume more restrictive conditions ab initio. It is not true, in general, that numerical representations of total preorders, when available, have some sort of linearity. The second remarkable fact is that the S functions for all the thermodynamic systems in the universe can be simultaneously calibrated (i.e., the multiplicative constants can be determined) in such a way that the entropies are additive, i.e., the S function for a compound system is obtained merely by adding the S functions of the individual systems, . To appreciate this fact it is necessary to recognize that the systems comprising a compound system can interact with each other in several ways, and therefore the possible adiabatic transitions in a compound are far more numerous than those allowed for separate, isolated systems. Nevertheless, the increase of the function continues to describe the adiabatic processes exactly—neither allowing more nor allowing fewer than actually occur. The statement does not require . The main problem, from our point of view, is this: What properties of adiabatic processes permit us to construct such a function? To what extent is it unique? What properties of the interactions of different systems in a compound system result in additive entropy functions?
In our opinion, the idea is to introduce some mathematical background to cope with systems that interact in Thermodynamics, giving rise to a new system. In this way, we should study the relationship (if any) between the entropy of the new system resulting from the interaction and the entropies of the systems we had at hand before. Cooper in [
18], as well as Lieb and Yngvasson in [
19], also add some axioms in order to deal with this sort of questions. Those additional axioms lean on additivity properties, and the aim here is finding entropy functions that are unique up to linear transformations. In a similar way, a battery of papers by Klimenko (see [
38,
73,
74,
75,
76,
77]) deals with concepts as mixing (see also [
78]) and competition of systems. It is not our intention here to make a criticism on those papers. However, to the eyes of a mathematician, it is difficult to isolate the definition of the concepts “mixing” and “competition”. Perhaps the idea of what is an abstract definition is totally different for mathematicians, physicists, chemists, engineers, economists or psychologists. It is quite typical that, instead of giving a rigorous abstract (mathematical) definition of a concept, some authors describe properties of the item they are analyzing. However, this provokes that the non-specialist (who, in particular, sometimes could be the pure mathematician), searching for a definition, is forced to make some interpretations, putting everything in a more abstract setting. Here are a few examples in which to draw a clear definition of what “mixing” and/or “competition” really is, constitutes a hard task for an interested but non-specialist researcher.
- (1)
Mixing is commonly understood as blending of two (or more) gases or liquids until a uniform mixture is achieved. Mixing preserves the identity of participating molecules and is thus different from chemical reactions. If molecules have little interactions, the resulting mixture is called an ideal mixture and characterized by maximal possible disorder and maximal possible entropy. Alternatively, interactions between molecules can reduce molecular chaos and the entropy of mixing falls below its maximal value.
- (2)
The process of mixing can be simulated by a sufficiently large number of notional particles, randomly walking from the region of their initial confinement and diffusing to occupy the whole domain. The fundamental similarity between diffusion (mixing) and random walks was established first in physics and then in mathematics.
- (3)
Typical processes of mixing are such that several systems of different composition, that are initially independent and separated one another, and such that each of them is in a thermodynamic state of chemical equilibrium, are mixed without chemical reaction. This is done by removal of the impermeable barriers and partition that separated the systems ab initio. After a time, a new thermodynamical state of internal equilibrium is reached in the new closed system.
- (4)
The idea of abstract competition was derived from the long-standing tradition of modeling turbulent combustion. In these models, it is common to use Pope particles (i.e., notional particles with properties and mixing). If conventional mixing is replaced by competitive mixing, these notional particles may be seen and used as computational incarnations of generic elements engaged in abstract competition. Competitive mixing can be deployed to characterize various processes: turbulent combustion, invasion waves and other related phenomena. Unlike conventional conservative mixing, competitive mixing can display complex behavior with sophisticated interdependencies, which is of special interest for this review.
- (5)
Competitive systems involve the process of competition in its most generic form. The elements of competitive systems compete with each other according to preset rules. The rules define the winners and losers for each competition round based on properties of the elements. The properties of the losers are lost while the winners utilize the resource vacated by the losers and duplicate their properties. The process of duplication is not perfect and involves random mutations, which are mostly detrimental for the competitiveness of the elements.
- (6)
Competitive systems, which are typically associated with complex stochastic behavior, are common in the real world. Abstract competition, which studies generic principles of competition in their most abstract form, can be interpreted as a form of mixing. This mixing, which is called competitive mixing, can be used to characterize various processes: turbulent combustion, invasion waves and other related phenomena. Unlike conventional conservative mixing, competitive mixing can display complex behavior with sophisticated interdependencies.
Remark 14. The previous paragraphs of Section 4 try to set and discuss a topic related to chemical potential that arose from exchange particles between systems. To the eyes of physicists, that concept can be described through Gibbs grand canonical ensemble theory (see [25,79,80]). However, mathematicians may still think that a further step in rigor is necessary here, therefore looking for clear definitions, at least in the mathematical background level on which that theory leans. Let us do here a mathematical interpretation to fix ideas:
In our opinion, the key mathematical framework on which this kind of questions could be settled and analyzed is that of algebraic ordered structures. That is, when we are given an ordered structure (e.g., a nonempty set X endowed with a total preorder ≾), it may happen that X also has some additional structure of algebraic stuff that, hopefully, could be compatible with the ordering involved. To put an example, in the lexicographic plane , we may consider an operation of coordinatewise addition or sum of vectors, given by for all . Now, we may notice that there is a compatibility or interaction between the total order and the algebraic binary operation , namely , for every . In the case when an algebraic operation is compatible with the ordered structure, it is typical and natural to search for the existence of numerical representations (e.g., utility functions, entropies) that not only preserve the ordered structure, but they are algebraic homomorphisms too, say, on the additive real line . For instance, if X is a nonempty set endowed with a total preorder ≾ and a binary operation, say ∗, such that holds true for every , we could be interested in finding a numerical representation u for ≾ such that, in addition, it also accomplishes that for every .
As commented in depth, e.g., in [
81], in Mathematics two different but finally converging approaches could lead to the study of algebraic ordered structures. On the one hand, as in the present paper, we encounter some ordered structure where it also arises an extra algebraic operation, compatible in some way with the ordering. In this former situation, the starting point is the ordered structure, and the algebra appears (last but not least) as something additional. On the other hand, we may deal with algebraic structures (e.g., a group, a semigroup, and a vector space) that are endowed with some kind of ordering that is compatible in some way with that, given at origin, algebraic structure. In other words, in this second situation, we begin with an algebraic structure, and the ordering is something additional, but not of minor importance.
Coming back to the entropy setting in Thermodynamics, we could understand “mixing” as some kind of interaction between systems. That is, if S is the state system, two different systems could interact in some way giving rise to a new system . Thus, it seems natural to understand the interaction as a binary operation, say ∘, on the set S (i.e., ), and consequently write . Depending on the properties of the interaction ∘, and assuming that an accessibility relation ⇝ is defined on S, we could be interested in finding an entropy function f that not only represents ⇝ but, in addition, it satisfies that holds true for every .
With respect to “competition”, we can also understand that notion as arising under the same mathematical setting as the aforesaid for mixing. Let us consider an example not coming from Thermodynamics or entropy, but clearly equivalent to situations as reactions, combustion, etc., where a component, the loser, is absorbed (or vanished, or even neglected) by another one, the winner: Thus, suppose that an animal (e.g., a lion) is a predator and another one (e.g., a gazelle) is a prey. If both animals meet and fight, and the lion kills the gazelle and eats it, we may interpret this as a situation in which we start with a lion plus a gazelle, and we end just with one lion (perhaps stronger since it has got its meal) and no gazelle. If we represent this “fight”, by means of a suitable mathematical abstraction, as an operation ∘ defined on the animal world, and l (respectively, g) denotes the lion (respectively, the gazelle), we would write something as . Similar situations appear in Thermodynamics when systems interact or compete in a way that one of them is a winner, the other is a loser, and the final result is that the first system survives (maybe with richer properties) while the second disappears. In any case, they could also be mathematically interpreted by means of a state system S where some binary operation ∘ is defined, eventually allowing cases as for some . Whenever S is endowed with an accessibility relation ⇝, we may also be interested in finding entropy functions that also could, in some way, give further information about the “competition” operation ∘ on S.
Therefore, we may conclude this discussion by saying that we should pay attention to ordered structures endowed with some compatible algebraic operation, and look for numerical representations (if any) that not only preserve the ordered structure, but also the algebraic one as well.
At this stage, another important fact is to select the suitable algebraic structure to deal with. In this sense, we point out that, in the literature on numerical representations of ordered structures (mainly, total preorders) endowed with some compatible algebraic operation, one may encounter, mainly, classical results on ordered groups and semigroups (see, e.g., [
81,
82,
83,
84,
85,
86,
87,
88,
89,
90,
91,
92,
93,
94,
95,
96,
97,
98,
99,
100,
101,
102,
103,
104]). A key reference here is the book by L. Fuchs [
105] However, there are also deep studies on lattices, where a famous reference is the book [
106] by Garret Birkhoff (see also [
107]), ordered vector spaces (see, e.g., [
108,
109,
110,
111,
112]) and even real algebras (see, e.g., [
56]).
To go ahead in our study, to choose an adequate algebraic setting, it still seems necessary to observe some features of the systems we want to analyze then. Thus, let us assume that we have in mind the idea of a thermodynamical approach related to mixing or competition processes, so that the state space
S is equipped with some binary operation, say ∘. In fact, such operation represents “mixing”, being understood, so-to-say, as the removal of the impermeable barriers that separated two given systems
, so allowing them to a composition, an interaction or competition (e.g., a chemical reaction). Thus, we think that the most suitable starting point here is assuming that
is a semigroup (see Definition 8). As already commented in [
1], it seems more plausible to interpret the state space as a semigroup rather than a group, because there are many chemical reactions that cannot be reverted, so that the concept of a “converse element” that would be compulsory to deal with the mathematical structure of an algebraic group could be nonsensical in this approach. However, the idea of the mixing (composition and reaction) being associative seems to be more suitable: if we admit that the composition of systems by mixing is a binary operation ∘ defined on
S (understood as the collection of all possible systems), it is quite natural to assume that the operation ∘ is associative (and perhaps commutative, too).
Remark 15. It is noticeable that these conditions were not commented in Section 4 in [18] nor (more than thirty years later) in the survey [19], despite of being implicitly assumed or taken for granted. In [18] some new axioms were added to the Carathéodory setting to deal with entropy functions that also preserve sone algebraic structure. The use of axioms to deal with numerical representations of, say, total preordered sets endowed with some compatible algebraic structure, in a way that the representation or utility function is an algebraic homomorphism (usually called additive) was launched in a pioneer work by O. Ḧolder (see [82,105]). Since then, it has also appeared in several other multidisciplinary settings, e.g., the theory of extensive measurement in Mathematical Psychology (see, e.g., [96,101]). However, its mathematical background is exactly the same as the one encountered when dealing with “additive entropies” in Thermodynamics, as in [18,19,113,114]. By the way, Cooper’s approach in [18] is actually more sophisticated, since he considers n-ary operations (instead of just a binary operation ∘
) to cope with composition of systems. However, we might still assume, at least implicitly, that the special kind of n-ary operations considered in [18] could be decomposed in a way as an ad hoc iteration of binary compositions. Definition 8. A semigroup is an algebraic structure that consists of a nonempty set S endowed with an internal binary operation ∘ that is associative. If, in addition, S has a null element e such that holds true for every , then is said to be a monoid. Furthermore, if each element s of a monoid has an inverse such that , then is said to be a group. A semigroup endowed with a total preorder ≾ is said to be a totally preordered semigroup if there is a compatibility between the total preorder ≾ and the binary operation ∘ such that holds true for every . (This last property is also known as the translation-invariance of the total preorder ≾ as regards the binary operation ∘). Notice that, in particular, a totally preordered semigroup is always cancellative, namely A totally preordered semigroup is said to be positive (respectively, negative) if (respectively, if ) holds true for every . In addition, an element is said to be positive (respectively, negative) if (respectively, if ) holds. If is a totally preordered semigroup, its subset (respectively, ) is said to be the positive cone (respectively, the negative cone) of . Notice that, when S is a totally preordered monoid, an element is positive (respectively, negative) if and only if (respectively, if ) holds, where e stands for the null element of the monoid.
Remark 16. If is a totally preordered semigroup, where ≾, we might pass to be working with a quotient space whose elements are the indifference classes of the elements of S with respect to ∼. That is, given , its corresponding class is the set . Since there is a compatibility between the total preorder ≾ and the binary operation, the quotient inherits a structure of totally ordered semigroup by considering in a natural way that the binary operation ∘ as well as ≾ directly act on the indifference classes that ∼ induces on S.
By this reason, henceforward we work with totally ordered semigroups, instead of totally preordered semigroups, unless otherwise stated.
Definition 9. A totally preordered semigroup is called additively representable if there exists a real-valued function satisfying that and also hold true for every . A map u with these properties is said to be an additive utility function.
To characterize the totally ordered semigroups that are additively representable, we still need to introduce the following definition.
Definition 10. A positive semigroup is said to be Archimedean if for every with , there exists a natural number such that . Moreover, it is called super-Archimedean if for every such that there exists a natural number such that .
In the case of a totally ordered group, a classical result coming from Algebra, and stated by Hölder early in 1901, characterizes the additive representability in terms of Archimedeaness, as follows (see [
82] or [
106], p. 300).
Proposition 1. A totally ordered group is additively representable if and only if its positive cone is Archimedean.
In the case of a totally ordered semigroup, the additive representability was characterized by N. G. Alimov in 1950, in terms of the super-Archimedean property, as follows (see [
94,
97] or the reference-note 21 on p. 26 in [
12]).
Proposition 2. A totally ordered semigroup is additively representable if and only if its positive cone is super-Archimedean and its negative cone is also super-Archimedean when endowed with the transpose order given by .
Remark 17. - (i)
The property of Archimedeaness on positive totally ordered semigroups does not suffice to guarantee the existence of an additive utility function. An example is the semigroup , equipped with the lexicographic total order and the binary operation . As already commented in Section 3, this ordered set is not representable, even if we do not pay attention to additivity (see, e.g., [106], pp. 200–201). - (ii)
A positive super-Archimedean totally ordered semigroup is, in particular, Archimedean. (For a detailed proof, see, e.g., [97].) However, the converse claim is not true in general: indeed endowed with the lexicographic ordering is not super-Archimedean since, for instance, but . - (iii)
If is an Archimedean totally ordered group, its positive cone is Archimedean and also its negative cone is Archimedean with respect to the transpose order (see, e.g., [97] for a proof and further details, as well as related properties).
Back to the consideration of a thermodynamical setting related to a mixing process, we may summarize the previous facts by claiming that, for the existence of an additive entropy the following extra axioms should be added to the Carathéodory ones, in the spirit of Section 4 in [
18]:
- (i)
The phase system S, endowed with the mixing operation ∘ and the accessibility relation ⇝ must be a totally preordered semigroup.
- (ii)
Both the positive cone, and the negative cone endowed with the transpose of the accessibility relation, of the totally ordered semigroup structure , must be super-Archimedean.
To complete the panorama, and following the set of ideas in [
1], we should also observe that a totally ordered group
could also be endowed with some topology
. In that case, it is natural to search for the existence of additive utility functions that are continuous with respect to the topology
on
S, and the usual Euclidean topology on the real line. Thus, provided that some topology
is at hand, we could deal with ideas related to limits, proximity or continuity and related items.
Remark 18. In the thermodynamical setting, questions of this kind, namely the existence of continuous and additive entropies, were already considered in Section 4 of Cooper’s key paper [18]. Let us analyze now the main results arising in the mathematical background of this approach.
Remark 19. Even being representable by an additive utility function, a totally ordered semigroup could fail to admit a continuous and additive representation. An example is the semigroup with the usual sum and order of the reals as binary operation, and equipped with the relative topology inherited from the usual one in . It can be proved (see, e.g., [98,99]) that the main reason for the non-existence of an additive and continuous representation is the discontinuity with respect to the order topology, of the sum in Z. Definition 11. A topological semigroup is a semigroup equipped with a topology τ that is related to the binary operation ∘ in the following sense: it makes continuous the binary operation that maps the pair to the element . (Here, on we consider the product topology coming from τ on S.)
A totally ordered semigroup is called a topological totally ordered semigroup when ∘ is continuous with respect to the order topology on S (and its corresponding product topology on ).
A topological group is defined as a group endowed with a topology τ such that the binary operation ∘ is continuous, and also the unary operation of taking inverses in G, that assigns to each element its inverse is also continuous with respect to the topology τ in G.
Remark 20. A famous result, extremely important in this approach, is due to Nyikos and Reichel (see [87]) and states that any totally ordered group is topological with respect to the order topology. It actually proves that on a totally ordered group , both the operation ∘ and the unary operation of taking an inverse are, a fortiori, continuous as regards the order topology . Notice that this is indeed a theorem about “automatic continuity”, in the sense that the compatibility between the total order ≾ and the algebraic operation ∘ already carries the continuity of the group operations, namely ∘ and the unary one of taking inverses, with respect to any natural topology for ≾ defined on G. However, the analogous result for semigroups is not valid in general. (The counterexample shown in Remark 19 also fits well here.)
The following result, whose proof appears in [
98], is perhaps the best one that one could expect to find in this approach.
Theorem 3. Let be a topological totally ordered semigroup. Assume also that S is endowed with a topology τ that is natural with respect to the linear order ≾. Suppose also that the positive cone is super-Archimedean with respect to ≾, whereas the negative cone is super-Archimedean with respect to the transpose order. Then, S is representable by an additive utility function such that and hold true for every , and, in addition, the map u is continuous with respect to the given topology τ in S and the usual one in .
To finish
Section 4, coming back once more to the thermodynamical approach, we may draw the conclusion that, for the existence of a continuous additive entropy. we could add the following suitable extra axioms to the Carathéodory-Cooper’s setting analyzed in Section 4 of Cooper’s paper [
18]:
- (i)
The state space S, equipped with the mixing operation ∘ and the accessibility relation ⇝ should be a totally ordered semigroup.
- (ii)
Both the positive cone, and the negative cone endowed with the transpose of the accessibility relation, of the totally ordered semigroup structure , should be super-Archimedean.
- (iii)
S should be endowed with a topology that is natural with respect to the accessibility relation ⇝. (In other words: ≾ should be continuous as regards .)
- (iv)
The structure should be a topological totally ordered semigroup. (That is, ∘ should be continuous with respect to the order topology on S and the product topology on .)
5. Representability of Interval Orders and Semiorders
Again, we follow some ideas already launched e.g., in [
1]. To start with, we define the representability of interval orders. Since the representability of a binary relation
on a nonempty set
X through a function
such that
forces
to be a total preorder, as already commented at the beginning of
Section 3, the numerical representations of other kinds of orderings (as interval orders or semiorders) compulsorily need some variation in the way we represent them. In the case of interval orders, the classical representations (when available) use two real-valued functions instead of just one, as stated in the next Definition 12.
Definition 12. Let X stand for a nonempty set. An interval order ≺ defined on X is called representable (as an interval order) if there exists a pair of real-valued functions accomplishing that . The pair is called a utility pair representing ≺, also known as a numerical representation of the given interval order ≺.
Remark 21. Notice that since an interval order ≺ is an asymmetric binary relation on X, if it is representable by means of a pair then we have a fortiori that holds for every . This gives rise to the following interpretation, that quite probably inspired the term of an interval order in the specialized literature. This term is attributed to Peter C. Fishburn (see [42,43]): Whenever the interval order ≺ admits a numerical representation by means of a pair , each element can be put in direct relationship with an interval of the real line. (Observe also that such interval could degenerate to a single point if .) Here, means that the interval is located on the real line totally on the left of the interval without touching it. To characterize the numerical representability of interval orders, we introduce now more necessary definitions.
Definition 13. Associated to an interval order ≺ defined on a nonempty set X, we shall consider two new binary relations.
These binary relations are said to be the traces of ≺. They are, respectively, denoted by (left trace) and (right trace), and defined as follows: for some , and similarly for some
Remark 22. We denote , , and and . Notice that the binary relation (respectively, ) is the adjoint of (respectively, of ). Both of these adjoints are indeed total preorders on X. Moreover, the indifference relation ∼ associated to the interval order ≺ is transitive if and only if , and ≾ coincide. In this case, ≾ is actually a total preorder on X. The converse is also true, and all these claims are also equivalent to say that the associated symmetric binary relation ≾ is transitive (see, e.g., [45] as well as Proposition 1.6.11 in [44] for further information). Definition 14. Let X be a nonempty set. An interval order ≺ defined on X is said to be interval order separable if there exists a countable subset such that for every with there exists such that .
The following key fact, that characterizes the numerical representability of interval orders is well-known in this literature (for a detailed proof, as well as other equivalent results, see, e.g., [
45]).
Theorem 4. An interval order ≺ defined on a nonempty set X is representable if and only if it is interval order separable.
Remark 23. Other characterizations, that use a more sophisticated set of conditions that are equivalent to the representability of an interval order, had already been obtained earlier by Fishburn in 1973 (see [115]) and, independently, by Doignon et al. in 1984 (see [116]). In the case of semiorders, apart from its possible representation just as interval-orders as stated in Definition 12, the classical numerical representations (when they exist) consist of a real-valued function plus a strictly positive constant.
Definition 15. Let ≺ denote a semiorder defined on a nonempty set X. We say that ≺ is representable in the sense of Scott and Suppes (see [40,117]) when there is a real-valued function and a strictly positive constant such that holds true for every . The pair is then said a Scott–Suppes pair representing ≺. Remark 24. If the semiorder ≺ is representable in the sense of Scott and Suppes by means of the pair , it is also Scott–Suppes representable by the pair , where is defined by . In other words, in the definition of Scott–Suppes representability of a semiorder, we can take without loss of generality.
At this stage, notice once more that “k” acts here as a threshold of discrimination. In fact, in suitable settings it could also be interpreted as a “quantum”.
To characterize the Scott–Suppes representability of semiorders, we need to introduce the next key definition.
Definition 16. Let X be a nonempty set. A semiorder ≺ defined on X is called regular with respect to sequences if there are no and sequences of elements in the set X such that happens nor, dually, holds true. In other words, the given set X never contains, as regards the given semiorder ≺, any infinite up chain with an upper bound, nor else any infinite down chain with a lower bound.
The Scott–Suppes representability of semiorders is finally characterized as follows (see, e.g., [
117,
118,
119,
120]):
Theorem 5. A semiorder ≺ defined on a nonempty set X is representable in the sense of Scott and Suppes if and only if it is interval order separable and regular with respect to sequences.
Remark 25. The obtention of a characterization of the representability of semiorders by means of conditions that, as the ones in the statement of Theorem 5 has been a truly “tour de force”. It was posed as an open problem in [39,40,121] among other classical papers. Since then, several other characterizations were achieved, some of them only valid for particular cases (see, e.g., [118,122,123,124,125,126]). A next step here would be the analysis of the
continuous representability of interval orders and semiorders, provided that the nonempty set
X on which an interval order or a semiorder ≺ has been defined is also endowed with some topology
. Unfortunately, in these cases (namely interval orders and semiorders) an analogous result to the famous Debreu’s open gap lemma (see Lemma 1 in
Section 3 above) is, in general, no longer available (see, e.g., [
127]). In fact, in the case of semiorders, the analogous of the Debreu’s open gap lemma is false in general, as proved in Example 1 and Remark 7 in [
128].
Unlike the case of total preorders, a characterization, valid for the general case, of the continuous representability of interval orders is not known yet. The same happens for semiorders.
At this stage, we need to introduce some mathematical background about the continuous representability of interval orders.
Definition 17. Let X be a nonempty set equipped with a topology τ and an interval order≺. The topology τ is said to be natural as regards ≺ if, for all , the sets and, finally, are all open sets in the topology τ.
When we are given an interval order ≺ on a topological space
in which the topology
is natural, the following important partial answer the problem of characterizing the continuous representability of an interval order ≺ on a topological space
arises. The proof of this important result may be seen in [
46], Theorem 1 on pp. 310–312.
Theorem 6. Let X be a nonempty set endowed with a topology τ. Let ≺ be an interval order on X. Assume also that the topology τ is natural with respect to the interval order ≺. The following statements are equivalent:
- (i)
The interval order ≺ is interval order separable.
- (ii)
The interval order ≺ is representable through a pair of continuous real-valued functions such that, in addition, U represents the total preorder and V represents the total preorder .
Remark 26. As far as we know, the result stated in Theorem 6 is the best one on the continuous representability of interval orders obtained until now. Nevertheless, Theorem 6 is only a partial answer to the still unsolved problem of characterizing the continuous representability of an interval order. This is due to the fact that nothing has been said about the possibility of the existence of a pair of continuous functions representing ≺ but such that either u does not represent or v does not represent . In this direction, some further discussion can be seen in Section 3 in [129], where other (still partial) solutions to the problem of characterizing the continuous representability of interval orders have been achieved. These are based on topological conditions different from the ones involved in the main results launched in [46]. Concerning the continuous representability of semiorders, in [128] some partial characterizations have recently been obtained, too. To conclude
Section 5, we still should pay attention to the representability of interval orders and semiorders defined on a nonempty set
X where some additional algebraic structure (e.g., a semigroup) appears, and, in some sense, it is compatible with the ordering.
However, and perhaps to our surprise, the existence of additive representations of an interval order ≺ defined on a nonempty set X may actually force the interval order to degenerate, so that its adjoint is a total preorder, as next Theorem 7 shows.
Theorem 7. Let S be a nonempty set endowed with an associative binary operation ∘. (That is: the structure is a semigroup.) Let ≺ be an interval order defined on S. Assume that ≺ is compatible with ∘ in the following sense: holds true for every ). Then, if the interval order ≺ admits a representation by means of a pair such that, in addition, both u and v are additive (i.e., hold true for every ), then ≾ is indeed a total preorder. In particular, both ≾ and ∼ are transitive.
6. Intransitive Processes
Coming back to the thermodynamical approach, we pay attention to the reference [
73] as well as to Section 3 in [
1].
Most of the studies that we include in
Section 6 had already appeared in [
1]. However, since our intention is to furnish, throughout the present manuscript, a survey of results concerning the mathematical foundations of Entropy, we have decided to include them again in
Section 6 for the sake of completeness.
Thus, already in the abstract of the paper [
73], one reads that:
While conventional thermodynamics is constrained by its zeroth law and is fundamentally transitive, the transitivity of competitive thermodynamics depend on the transitivity of the competition rules. Intransitivities are common in the real world and are responsible for common behavior in competitive systems.
With similar ideas in mind, in [
38], it is claimed that:
While physical thermodynamics is always transitive, the same cannot be stated a priori about apparent thermodynamics.
Therefore, it is interesting at this stage to find a suitable mathematical approach in order to interpret intransitivities arising in state spaces.
A possible mathematical setting that may help us to do so was already introduced in the appendix of the reference [
73]. Nevertheless, neither in that study nor in the more recent [
38], the key notion of an interval order just defined and analyzed in
Section 2 and
Section 5 of the present manuscript has been used as a tool.
In our opinion, as already shown in [
1], to deal with intransitivities, the concept of an interval order is the key notion and the results on interval orders should be considered as the main device.
Remark 27. In fact, although they were already implicit in Wiener’s works (see [41]) under a different terminology, it is commonly accepted that interval orders were (re)-introduced later to understand better typical situations that arise in Psychology (Measurement Theory) or Economics (Utility Functions), where some intransitivities related to the concept of a preference were encountered in the corresponding models (see, e.g., [39,40,42,43,130]). Remember here that the indifference relation ∼ (or, equivalently, the relation ≾) associated to an interval order ≺ defined on a nonempty set X is transitive if and only if , and ≾ coincide, and in this case ≾ is actually a total preorder on X (see Definition 13). By the way, an interval order ≺ is always transitive. Only its associated relations ∼ and ≾ could fail to be transitive.
Example 2. In cases in which ∼ is not transitive, it is typical that some situations arising in, say, experiments or processes can be interpreted as paradoxical, so-to-say. For instance, in theoretical computer science, when several computers are working in distributed computation, we may pay attention, given a task x, to the interval of time in which the task x is being executed by the system of computers, so that (respectively, ) is the moment when the task x starts (respectively, finishes). Therefore, we can assign to each task its corresponding interval of time, and accordingly declare that a task x is “totally precedent” with respect to another task y, if . This precedence relation that we may denote ≺, is, obviously, a representable interval order. When two intervals corresponding to different tasks overlap, there are moments of time in which we could see both tasks being active (at the same time), so that we could interpret them as “simultaneous”. This corresponds to the associated relation ∼, which is not transitive in this case. The same occurs with the associated binary relation ≾, so that if we take ≾ (instead of the more restrictive ≺) as a binary relation that expresses also an idea of “precedence” (but weaker than before), the intransitivity of ≾ sounds as something “paradoxical”.
In fact, intransitivities of this kind can also occur in physical processes and/or chemical reactions: Thus, as already mentioned in [73], we have that: Intransitivities are possible in chemical reactions. The Belousov-Zhabotinsky reaction is known to display a cyclic chemical behavior in a homogeneous mixture, which is unusual since most chemical kinetics tend to monotonically converge to an equilibrium or steady state. (...) The simplest chemical kinetic scheme that can adequately simulate the Belousov-Zhabotinsky reaction is Oregonator [131]. This scheme involves an essential intransitivity. Remember that, if the accessibility relation of the state space is a total preorder, this kind of intransitivities would never occur.
Moreover, as explained in [
73]:
The choice in favor of considering intransitivities needs to be made not because intransitivity can immediately explain all the complexities of the surrounding world but because transitive competition certainly cannot. This does not prevent many specific features from having perfectly transitive explanations, while intransitivity is associated with more complex effects. (...) It is worthwhile, however, to draw the attention of the reader to the immediate unresolved problems associated with intransitive behavior.
In addition, in [
76], the author claims that:
When treated simplistically, intransitivity may seem to be illogical but, nevertheless, it is common in nature and needs to be studied.
Taking into account these last comments encountered in the aforementioned references, as well as the study made in Section 3 in [
1], we can give some answers to the problem of intransitive behavior encountered in several physical or chemical processes. To do so, our main tools are the concept of an interval order and its numerical representability through two real-valued functions, when available. Thus, the main results introduced in
Section 5 above can indeed be used to explain typical intransitivities observed in Thermodynamics, when dealing with physical or chemical processes.
Remark 28. However, in Section 6, bearing in mind the results launched in Section 5, we are going to interpret only the case of intransitivities that derive from an interval order. Those intransitivities could be dealt with by means of two different entropy functions. However, when the intransitivity is of a totally different nature, the corresponding study remains open. At this stage, we should notice that, obviously, not all the intransitive binary relations that may be defined on a nonempty set are related to interval orders in some way. There are other different kinds of intransitivity, that we do not consider in the present manuscript. To start with, let us notice first that the numerical representability of an interval order ≺ on a nonempty set X, by means of a pair of real-valued functions such that holds true for every has already been characterized in Theorem 4, through the condition of interval order separability.
However, nothing has been said yet concerning the possibility of interpreting Theorem 4 in a thermodynamical setting, in terms of entropies. For instance, we may wonder if the functions that appear in a pair that represents the interval order ≺ are indeed entropies in some interpretation ad hoc.
A starting point to give a positive answer to the last question is the interpretation of the traces associated to an interval order ≺ on a nonempty set
X. As previously stated in Definition 13,
for some
, and
for some
A glance at the last expressions shows that
(respectively,
) appears as the composition “
” (respectively, “
”) of two binary relations on
X. Remember also that their associated relations
and
are actually total preorders on the given set
X (see, e.g., [
45]).
Given , we may observe that . However, the negation of just states that there is no such that . In other words, for any it holds true that . Calling , we arrive at . Similarly, we also have that , and here the negation of tells us that there is no such that . Equivalently, for all it holds true that . Hence, calling , we get that .
If ≺ is representable through a pair
, this kind of representation can still be improved, as stated in the next crucial Theorem 8 that refines Theorem 4 in
Section 5.
Theorem 8. Let X be a nonempty set. Let ≺ stand for an interval order defined on the given set X. The following statements are equivalent:
- (i)
The interval order ≺ is representable through a pair of real-valued functions (i.e., holds true for every ).
- (ii)
The interval order ≺ is representable through a pair of real-valued functions, with the additional property that U represents the total preorder (that is, ), while V represents the total preorder (i.e., holds true for every ).
Proof. See [
45], Theorem 1 on pp. 175–181. ☐
Remark 29. This Theorem 8 is not stating that any numerical representation of ≺ is such that u represents and v represents . Instead, it is said is that if there is a pair that represents the interval order ≺, then there is another one (perhaps different!) with U representing and V representing . By the way, notice that, unlike Theorem 6, Theorem 8 does not involve continuity.
Going back to the thermodynamical approach, let us now discuss how this last result, namely Theorem 8, can actually be conciliated in a way with Carathéodory’s axiomatics, in order to study situations when the accessibility relation on the state space
S is intransitive. As already implicitly suggested in [
73], to interpret certain processes, perhaps more than one entropy should be considered.
In Klimenko’s own words (see [
73]):
In non-equilibrium phenomena, the production of physical entropy is typically high, in perfect argument with the laws of thermodynamic. Although no direct violation of the laws of thermodynamics is known, thermodynamics struggles to explain complexity, which is often observed in essentially non-equilibrium phenomena: turbulent mixing and combustion as well as evolution of life forms may serve as typical examples. The entropy of turbulent fluctuations does not seem to be maximal and the same applies to entropies characterizing distributions in other complex non-equilibrium processes. These entropies have similarities with but are not the same as the molecular entropy, which characterizes disorder of molecular movements and is subject to the laws of thermodynamics. We use the term apparent entropy to distinguish entropy-like quantities from the molecular entropy.
This key idea, namely the use of more than one entropy seems to support also the observation made in [
38], already mentioned before, namely:
Physical thermodynamics is always transitive, but the same cannot be stated a priori about apparent thermodynamics.
In other words, it seems that in several processes at least two (instead of just one) different kinds of thermodynamical behavior, that we may call “physical” and “apparent” are involved. Thus, it seems adequate to consider, too, two different but closely related kinds of entropy instead of just one. In our opinion, hopefully this could help a physicist or a chemist to interpret and understand better practical situations where some kind of intransitivity is observed.
In the study made in [73], concerning thermodynamical behavior of intransitive competition, it is said that competition is intransitive if at least one intransitive triplet arises. Klimenko [73] then claims that: Generally, a consistent ranking cannot be introduced for intransitive competition, but ranking can often be assigned to subdomains if the competition is transitive within these subdomains. It should be noted, however, that the rankings assigned in different subdomains would result in multi-valued functions and can not be made fully consistent with each other when the competition is intransitive.
Unlike Klimenko’s approach in [
73], we should point out here that Theorem 8 carries the following important suggestions:
- (i)
Instead of just one ranking, we would need to use two. One of them is given by U and the other one comes from by V.
- (ii)
Both functions U, V act on the whole domain. It is unnecessary to consider here subdomains of transitivity of the interval order given a priori on the set X.
- (iii)
The functions U and V can be understood as “fully consistent” one another. They are interdependent because they represent, jointly, the given interval order.
Coming back to the thermodynamical setting once more, now we may suppose that the state space
S is equipped with an accessibility relation (asymmetric in this case), say ↪, that is now an interval order. We may now consider its traces and their corresponding adjoints. Remember that those adjoints are total preorders on the phase system
S. This would allow us to use the Carathéodory axioms independently for each of the adjoints of the traces of ↪ in order to find entropy functions that represent them, asumming that the condition of perfect separability, necessary to warrant the existence of a utility function that represents a total preorder, as stated in Theorem 1, is accomplished by both such adjoints. Thus, this approach is consistent with the set of axioms due to Carathéodory and Cooper (see [
18]), the classical one in Thermodynamics.
However, using the theory on interval orders we can actually go further. Theorem 8 actually allows us to construct both entropy functions at the same time, and with the additional conditions that the pair represents ↪ and, in addition, holds for every so that U and V could indeed be interpreted as a pair of entropies such that one of them dominates (i.e., is bigger than) the other, as in the typical case of apparent entropy vs. molecular entropy encountered in physical and chemical processes.
Hence, to deal with intransitivities in a reasonable way by means of an intertwined pair of entropy functions, we need that the state space S endowed with the binary relation ↪ be an interval order that satisfies the separability condition. Finally, if we are also interested in continuous representations for ↪ with respect to some topology on the phase system S, a reasonably good restriction on the topology is that be natural as regards the interval order ↪. In that case Theorem 6 is of capital importance in this setting.
Therefore, following [
1] and summarizing all the ideas presented in
Section 6, we point out to the physicist or chemist the following suggestions in order to analyze a process in which some intransitivity could be noticed:
- (i)
If a chemical or physical process shows intransitivities, two entropy functions instead of just one should be used.
- (ii)
One of these two entropy functions should be smaller than the other one.
- (iii)
Once both entropy functions have been obtained and identified (this depends on the process considered), try to interpret the intransitivity observed by means of of a representable interval order that models the accessibility relation.
- (iv)
Other features that could occur aside the intransitivity observed in a chemical or physical process may depend on other different additional mathematical structure. Thus, to analyze questions related to mixing and competition the consideration of some algebraic structure (e.g., a semigroup) could be necessary. In addition, to handle continuity, connectedness or metrizability among other possible features, the use of some topological notions is compulsory.
- (v)
It is also crucial to identify the mathematical nature of the process to be analyzed. Whereas the mere intransitivity has to do with mathematical ordered structures, mixing and competition force the intervention of algebraic structures, and continuity needs some topology being defined on the state space. Of course, all these mathematical structures do not work independently from each other: they interact in the processes considered, but in a way that each of them, separately, is mainly responsible for some particular aspect of our interest (e.g., intransitivity).
7. The Construction of Numerical Representations of Ordered Structures
A further glance at
Section 2 with all the preliminaries related to entropy reminds us again that most of the usual definitions of entropy that arise in the frame of the laws of Thermodynamics are given through some integrals.
We could say that this fact comes, and it is justified too, from physical evidence, experiments, etc. Therefore, the mathematical background on entropies acts only as a basis (that maybe we can consider a cornerstone), to justify in an abstract and rigorous manner all what, say, a physicist or a chemist is observing in her/his laboratory.
Well, even if all this is formally correct, we may still wonder about the possibility of constructing numerical representations of orderings that are got in terms of some mathematical integral.
To fix ideas, we could start by considering a representable total preorder ≾ defined on a nonempty set X. Thus, we know that ≾ admits a utility function that represents it. In fact, if X is endowed with a topology that is natural with respect to it is also possible to find a numerical representation of ≾ that is continuous with respect to the topology on X and the usual Euclidean topology on the real line.
However, now the question is:
Can some numerical representation of ≾ be built in a natural way through some kind of integral?
What about continuous utility functions for ≾?.
This is far from easy!
Here, we should pay attention to the constructions of numerical representations for total preorders that have already been introduced in the literature (e.g., Utility Theory, Entropy, etc.).
Concerning numerical representations of total preorders, some classical constructions appear in [
106] and also in the first four chapters of Reference [
44], among many other sources.
Thus, for the particular case in which the nonempty set
X is finite, and it is endowed with a total (linear) order ⪯, given
we may define
as the cardinality of the set
. It is then clear that
holds true for any
. This construction is very old indeed. It essentially appears in Cantor’s famous papers [
132,
133]. George Cantor is considered as the pioneer of the search for numerical representation of ordered structures.
Remark 30. When working with numerical representations of different classical of orderings (e.g., total preorders, interval orders and semiorders) defined on finite sets, the mathematical techniques mainly come from Combinatorics (an excellent book in this direction is [134]). However, when working with infinite sets, the techniques are quite different, and are based on General Topology, Real Analysis, etc. An excellent book in this setting is [44]. Now, suppose that
X is infinite but countable, say
and it is endowed with a total order ≺. In this case, we define a suitable function
as follows:
Again, it is straightforward to see that , so u is a utility function that represents ⪯.
When
X is infinite (but maybe it is uncountable now), and ⪯ is a perfectly separable total order on
X, first we take a countable subset
such that given
with
there exists
such that
(see Theorem 1 in
Section 3). Then, we represent the restriction of ⪯ to the countable subset
D by means of a suitable series, as before. Finally, a utility function
u defined on
D can be extended to the whole set
X. To do so, given
we may define
. We may prove that this extension defines a numerical representation for ⪯ on the set
X.
From the point of view of continuity, provided that
X is endowed with some topology
that is natural with respect to the total order
X, all the above constructions, based on series, are troublesome. The reason is that they give rise to discontinuities at each
. This is really a pity, because it forces us to use other different techniques if we want to have at hand continuous utility functions. At this stage, the famous Debreu’s open gap lemma (see Lemma 1 in
Section 3) comes to our rescue. Through that key result, we can finally build a continuous utility function representing ⪯. However, almost all the known proofs of Lemma 1 are quite difficult, and unintuitive in the sense that the construction is too theoretical and far beyond a possible visualization of it.
Anyway, by means of Debreu’s open gap lemma we warrant the existence of continuous utility functions. However, this does not solve our former question yet, since we do not know whether or not such new continuous utility function appears as a suitable integral.
Again, a new step is necessary. Thus, if is a utility function that represents ⪯ and is continuous with respect to the order topology on X and the usual topology on the real line, by composing u with another suitable continuous an strictly increasing function we may consider without loss of generality that u takes values in . Then, we can “transport” the Lebesgue measure on the unit interval , to the set X, as follows: By definition, now a measurable set of X is a subset such that is Lebesgue-measurable. In this way, we could interpret as the “transported” measure of Y. In this way, the Lebesgue integral on could also be transported to X by means of the utility function u.
As can be seen, all this needs too many steps, and our intuition could be lost in the process. However, at least, we may say that it is theoretically possible to have at hand continuous ad hoc numerical representations of total orders that are defined by means of some integral.
To conclude
Section 7, we point out that in the specialized literature about numerical representations of ordered structures, the use of integrals to define utility functions is quite scarce. (See e.g., [
44,
64,
65,
67,
90]).