Next Article in Journal
Boundedness and Compactness of Weighted Composition Operators from α-Bloch Spaces to Bers-Type Spaces on Generalized Hua Domains of the First Kind
Next Article in Special Issue
Evolutionary Model of Signed Edges in Online Networks Based on Infinite One-Dimensional Uniform Lattice
Previous Article in Journal
Efficient Trajectory Planning for Optimizing Energy Consumption and Completion Time in UAV-Assisted IoT Networks
Previous Article in Special Issue
Hybrid Modeling of Anxiety Propagation in Response to Threat Stimuli Flow
 
 
Font Type:
Arial Georgia Verdana
Font Size:
Aa Aa Aa
Line Spacing:
Column Width:
Background:
Article

On the Concept of Equilibrium in Sanctions and Countersanctions in a Differential Game

by
Vladislav I. Zhukovskiy
1 and
Lidiya V. Zhukovskaya
2,*
1
Faculty of Computational Mathematics and Cybernetics, Lomonosov Moscow State University, Moscow 119991, Russia
2
Central Economics and Mathematics, Institute Russian Academy of Sciences, Moscow 117418, Russia
*
Author to whom correspondence should be addressed.
Mathematics 2023, 11(20), 4402; https://doi.org/10.3390/math11204402
Submission received: 5 August 2023 / Revised: 3 October 2023 / Accepted: 14 October 2023 / Published: 23 October 2023
(This article belongs to the Special Issue Modeling and Simulation of Social-Behavioral Phenomena)

Abstract

:
This paper develops the methodology for modeling decision processes in complex controlled dynamic systems. The idea of balancing such systems (driving them to equilibrium) is implemented, and a new mechanism for the equilibria’s stability is proposed. Such an approach involves economic–mathematical modeling jointly with systems analysis methods, economics, law, sociology, game theory, management, and performance measurement. A linear-quadratic positional differential game of several players is considered. Coefficient criteria under which the game has an equilibrium in sanctions and countersanctions and, simultaneously, no Nash equilibrium are derived. The economic and legal model of active equilibrium is studied through the legal concept of sanctions, which enlarges the practical application of this class of problems.

1. Introduction

A sanction (from Latin “sanction”—strictest decree) is a measure of influence applied to an economic agent (an individual or a legal entity, industry, or the state) and entailing certain consequences. Sanctions may be of an economic, legal, or social nature. In terms of form, a sanction may be expressed as a prohibition, restriction of operations, fines, and more. Depending on the nature of violated rights, it is customary to distinguish such legal sanctions as criminal, administrative, property, and international legal sanctions. At the same time, according to the consequences’ nature, legal norms’ sanctions can be both negative and positive. The first one implies the application of penalties, and the second one—actions of encouragement. Game Theory is actively used as a tool for modeling socio-economic processes in general and sanctions processes in particular, so, for example, in the research [1] based on a game-theoretic approach, the concept of a model of criminal sanctions and a model of criminal punishment system, corresponding to fundamental requirements of game theory, taking into account Nash’s equilibrium is offered. The author concludes that “the game-theoretic approach to the formation of both individual criminal law sanctions and the system of criminal law sanctions is quite applicable and complements the formal legal logic of construction of criminal law sanctions and their system, allows to avoid defects in the construction of criminal law sanctions and helps to eliminate legal uncertainty in sentencing”.
It is well known that social sanctions are commonly understood as measures of encouragement and punishment that stimulate an individual to comply with social norms. Sanctions can be formal (medals, diplomas, scholarships, fines, and others) and informal (praise, ridicule, boycott, and others), positive and negative. The research on social sanctions is beyond the scope of this work. Further, we will consider economic sanctions in detail, as much as possible, within the framework of this section.
The first economic sanctions recorded in written sources were imposed by the Athenian Maritime Union (Delos Symmachus) on the city of Megara (part of the Peloponnesian Union) in 432 BC in order to stop the practice of receiving runaway Athenian enslaved people in that city and plowing the sacred border territories. They are known as “Megarian psephism”. The effectiveness of the sanctions was not obvious. On the one hand, the Megarian merchants suffered significant losses, but on the other hand, they were forced to turn to their allies (primarily Sparta) for military support. As a result of the Peloponnesian War, Athens suffered a crushing defeat, and the Athenian alliance was destroyed. Studying the above fact and using it as an example, G. Tsebelis, in his article “Are Sanctions Effective? A Game-Theoretic Analysis” [2], reasoned that “Although economic sanctions have been quite frequent in the twentieth century, a close examination of the low success rate (33 out of 83 cases) indicates that sender countries are unable to select the appropriate cases. Moreover, analysts sometimes offer contradictory advice for such selection”. This research provides a game-theoretic explanation of these phenomena. Six different game-theoretic scenarios lead to the same equilibrium outcome. It is a mixed strategy equilibrium. The success ratio is the outcome of the selection of mixed strategies by sender and receiver countries. Under a wide range of (specified) circumstances, the size of the sanction has no impact on the behavior of the target country. Finally, some empirical implications of the game-theoretic analysis are compared to existing empirical generalizations, and further implications for empirical research are discussed.
In the Middle Ages in Europe, economic sanctions were primarily local and short-lived because of the constantly changing configuration of trade and military alliances and the changing interests of individual rulers and influential individuals. In the 19th century, the primary tool of economic sanctions was naval blockades—measures to prevent a country’s maritime trade with other countries without a declaration of war. Between 1827 (the first known naval blockade) and 1914, 21 blockades were recorded against Turkey, Portugal, the Netherlands, Colombia, Panama, Mexico, Argentina, and El Salvador. The organizers of the blockades were mainly Great Britain (12 times) and France (11 times), but also Italy and Germany (three times each), Russia and Austria (twice each), and Chile [3].
Economic sanctions became widespread in the twentieth century with the development of international trade relations. Before World War II, Yugoslavia, Greece, Bolivia, Paraguay, and Italy were subject to collective economic sanctions. During the Cold War, sanctions were largely ineffective because they were not supported by either the Western or Eastern blocs of countries (with the United States and the Soviet Union as leaders, respectively). Unified sanctions, supported by both blocs, were imposed only twice: on Rhodesia and South Africa, and according to international relations experts, in both cases, were not effective enough.
One of the best-known examples of collective economic sanctions at the time was the restriction of deliveries of “strategic” goods and technologies, primarily military and computer technology, to socialist countries. The Coordination Committee (CoCom) was created in 1949 specifically to control exports to the Eastern Bloc countries, which included 17 states, while another six countries cooperated with the committee without formally being part of it. The committee ceased its activities in 1994. The most famous example of long-term unilateral sanctions is the U.S. embargo against Cuba, which began in 1960–1962 and continues today. U.S. companies are prohibited from any economic contact with Cuba without special permission, including in third countries. According to Cuban authorities, direct damage from the embargo amounted to about USD 1 trillion in current prices. Nevertheless, the goal of U.S. economic sanctions—establishing democracy in Cuba—has not been achieved. Since 1990, the UN has made greater use of international economic sanctions against various states. They have been subjected to Iraq (since 1990), Yugoslavia (1991–2001), Somalia (since 1992), Libya (1992–2003), Liberia (since 1992), Angola (1993–2002), Haiti (1993–1994), Rwanda (1994–2008), Sierra Leone (since 1997), Afghanistan (since 1999), Eritrea and Ethiopia (since 2000), DR Congo (since 2003), Cǒte d’Ivoire (since 2004), Sudan (since 2004), Lebanon (since 2005), Iran (since 2006), and DPRK (since 2006). The sanctions are mostly partial and restrict weapons and military equipment supplies to these countries. In some cases, foreign assets are frozen [4,5].
Global economic sanctions have been repeatedly imposed on several states. Sanctions, whether international or unilateral, currently apply to 24 states worldwide. However, experience has shown that states subject to sanctions have almost always found ways to minimize their damage or use them to their advantage [6].
Many publications are devoted to economic sanctions and the application of the game-theoretic apparatus in their study. Let us note the research of Marc V. Simon “When sanctions can work: Economic sanctions and the theory of moves” [7]; Shidiqi, Khalifany Ash and Pradiptyo, Rimawan “A Game Theoretical Analysis of Economic Sanctions” [8]; Karimi, Mohammad and Maleki, Abbas and Haieri Yazdi, Asieh “How the Possibility of a Fight-Back Strategy Affects the Consequences of a Sanction’s Regime” [9]; Onder, Mehmet “The Impact of Decision-Makers on Economic Sanctions: A Game Theoretical Perspective” [10].
In contrast to other research, this article offers an economical and legal substantiation of theoretical and game constructions modeling the process of application of sanctions and countersanctions, using in general terms the idea of systemic balance of three macrosystems: economic, legal, and social [11]. In a particular case, the economic-legal substantiation of the proposed theoretical-game model of the balance of sanctions and countersanctions is based on the use of the legal concept of sanctions as a component of the definition of legal responsibility of subjects, i.e., in practical terms, the regulator implements the principle of inevitability of legal responsibility, in particular, sanctions for offense and crime (can be a departure from the established in the legal prescriptions rules, rules of social and economic relations), which is manifested in the application in the description of real socio-economic processes, various concepts of static and active equilibriums.
The current national market system is based on the neoliberal economic doctrine. In differentiated forms, it covers all public relations spheres and appears in decision processes at all complex control and controlled systems levels. Various concepts of static [12] and active equilibria [13] are adopted to balance controlled systems [14,15] in game-theoretic economic–mathematical modeling. If an analytically constructed differential game describes decision-making in a complex system, then, according to leading researchers, equilibrium as an acceptable solution of a differential game should have the property of stability [16,17,18]. In a practical interpretation, stability means no player will increase their payoff by any unilateral deviation from equilibrium.
Within the neoliberal economic doctrine, the well-known solution proposed by J. Nash [19,20,21,22] meets this requirement in many situations. (In 1994, J. Nash, J. Harsanyi and R. Selten were awarded the Nobel Prize in Economic Sciences “for the pioneering analysis of equilibria in the theory of non-cooperative games”). Note that this equilibrium does not always exist under certain conditions and (or) has several negative properties. For example, Nash equilibria can be internally and externally unstable. The mathematical problem of ensuring the stability of equilibria can be solved using active equilibria, e.g., the classical equilibrium in threats and counterthreats or the equilibrium in objections and counter-objections [23,24], simultaneously with requiring efficiency (Pareto maximality) [25,26,27].
The economic and legal justification of game-theoretic models generally uses the idea of system balancedness: complex controlled systems correlate through interaction, and balancedness means that the legal order of public relations corresponds to the laws and trends of economic development. In a particular case, the economic and legal justification of the equilibrium in sanctions and countersanctions is based on the legal concept of sanctions defining the legal responsibility of subjects (agents). In practical terms, the adjuster implements the principle of inevitable legal liability (particularly sanctions) for an offense and crime (any deviation from the behavioral rules established by legal regulations, e.g., any deviation from the equilibrium mentioned above).

2. Methods

The theoretical and methodological basis of the research is the theory of systems analysis, economics, theory of state and law, sociology, synthesis of the provisions and principles of economic and mathematical modeling, game theories, and management and developed on their basis the theoretical and game models of decision-making in complex systems with uncertainty.
Let us proceed to the conceptual framework used below. At the micro level, the concept of threat contains both a real action by a market participant and its possibility to compel the latter to comply with the previously established rules; at the macro level, the matter concerns “the threat of coercion”, i.e., a regulatory definition of the legal inevitability of punishment. In the legal literature, the threat of coercion means a sanction and refers to measures of impact applied in regulation [28,29]. In mathematical game theory, the terms “threat” and “sanction” can be used as a synonym for the word “objection” to mitigate their “aggressive” nature. The economic content of sanctions in legal sources includes measures of compulsory economic impact for violating the established procedure for activities and often have preventive, compensatory, and repressive functions. Accordingly, in the macro- and micromodels of decision-making, the player resisting coercion and using counter methods of impact is determined through counter objection, counter-threat, and countersanction.
Like other equilibria, the equilibrium in sanctions and countersanctions can yield stable solutions, but each concept uses different mechanisms. In the case of Nash equilibrium, all players, except for the deviating one, continue using the same strategies as before. In the case of equilibrium in sanctions and countersanctions, the players pass to the legally admissible actions that force the deviating player to follow the equilibrium: the players implement countersanctions. Hence, the inevitability of punishment is a good reason for the players to stay within such an equilibrium. From the legislative viewpoint, their actions rest on the concept of legal responsibility for changing the content of a current obligation and future negative consequences due to its violation [29].
As mentioned above, the classical concept of threats and counterthreats is not widespread in mathematical game theory [24] and is restricted to static or differential two-player games [30,31,32,33,34,35,36,37]. The approach presented below is novel for the theory of differential games:
  • We augment the equilibrium in sanctions and countersanctions with the property of Pareto maximality.
  • We identify a relatively large class of differential games of players in which there is an equilibrium in sanctions and countersanctions, and, at the same time, no Nash equilibrium exists.
  • We propose an algorithm for constructing the equilibrium in sanctions and countersanctions.

3. Results

To construct a game-theoretic model of equilibrium in sanctions and countersanctions, we consider a noncooperative linear-quadratic differential N-player game in normal form described by an ordered quadruple
Γ = , Σ , U i i , J i ( U , t 0 , x 0 i .
In the game Γ , the set of players (e.g., market participants) is = 1 , N , where N 2 . The dynamics of the controlled system Σ (the interacting subjects of market activity, also called agents) obey the vector linear differential equation
Σ ÷ x ˙ = A ( t ) x + u 1 + + u N , x ( t 0 ) = x 0 ,
with the following notations: x n is the n-dimensional state vector of the system Σ   t [ t 0 , ϑ ] is a finite time interval of the game with a fixed terminal time instant ϑ = c o n s t ;   u i n is the control action of player i  ( i ) ; ( t , x ) [ 0 , ϑ ] × n is a pair determining a current position in the game Γ ; finally, ( t 0 , x 0 ) as an initial position, where 0 t 0 < ϑ . The matrix A ( t ) of dimensions n × n is assumed to have continuous elements on [ 0 , ϑ ] , which is denoted by A ( ) C n × n [ 0 , ϑ ] .
The strategy U i of player i will be identified with an n-dimensional vector function u i ( t , x ) , and this fact will be denoted by U i ÷ u i ( t , x ) . Then, the strategy set of player i can be written as
U i = { U i ÷ u i ( t , x ) , u i ( t , x ) = Q i ( t ) x Q i ( ) C n × n [ 0 , ϑ ] } .
Thus, player i chooses their (strategy by specifying a matrix Q i ( t )   ( i ) of dimensions n × n from the space C n × n [ 0 , ϑ ] .
The game evolves over time under market competition in the following way. Without forming coalitions with other players, each player i chooses a particular strategy U i ÷ Q i ( t ) x , which yields a strategy profile  U = ( U 1 , , U N ) U = U 1 × × U N of the game. Next, each player finds the solution x ( t ) ,   t 0 t ϑ , of System (1) with u i = Q i ( t ) x   ( i ) , i.e.,
x ˙ ( t ) = [ A ( t ) + Q 1 ( t ) + + Q N ( t ) ] x ( t ) , x ( t 0 ) = x 0 .
The system of linear homogeneous differential Equation (2) with continuous coefficients on [ t 0 , ϑ ] has a continuous solution x ( t ) that is extendable to [ t 0 , ϑ ]   t 0 [ 0 , ϑ ) . Then, each player constructs the realization of their strategy u i [ t ] = Q i ( t ) x ( t )   ( i ) and the corresponding realization of the strategy profile u [ t ] = ( u 1 [ t ] , , u N [ t ] ) , which consists of the N continuous n-dimensional vectors u 1 [ t ] , , u N [ t ] on [ t 0 , ϑ ] . The payoff function of player i is a quadratic functional
J i ( U 1 , U N , t 0 , x 0 ) = x ( ϑ ) C i x ( ϑ ) + t 0 ϑ j u j [ t ] D i j u j [ t ] d t ( i )
defined on the continuous pairs ( x ( t ) , u [ t ] ) , t [ t 0 , ϑ ] . Without loss of generality, let the constants matrices C i and D i j of dimensions n × n be symmetric. The prime denotes transposition: x is a row vector. The value of the functional (3) is called the payoff of player i. The neoliberal economic doctrine assumes that each player in the game Γ seeks to maximize their payoff only.
This research aims to find a rather general class of noncooperative linear-quadratic differential N-player games in normal form Γ that have no Nash equilibrium but simultaneously have an equilibrium in sanctions and countersanctions. To this effect, we will associate with the game Γ the N-criteria dynamic choice problem
Γ v = Σ , U , { J i ( U , t 0 , x 0 ) } i .
Here, the controlled dynamic system Σ coincides with (1); the set of alternatives U coincides with the set of strategy profiles U = i = 1 N U i of the game Γ ; the N criteria J i ( U , t 0 , x 0 )   ( i ) are given by (3). The DM’s goal in the problem Γ v is to choose an alternative U P U for which the N criteria (3) will take the maximum possible values. V. Pareto proposed a conventional approach to such problems in 1909; see [38,39].
Note two results, which are immediate from Definition 1.
Definition 1.
An alternative  U P = ( U 1 P , , U N P ) U  is said to be Pareto-maximal in the problem  Γ v  if  U U  and  ( t 0 , x 0 ) [ 0 , ϑ ) × n ,   x 0 0 n ,  the system of inequalities
J i ( U , t 0 , x 0 ) J i ( U P , t 0 , x 0 ) ( i ) ,
with at least one strict inequality, is inconsistent. In this case, the vector  J P = J P [ t 0 , x 0 ] = ( J 1 ( U P , t 0 , x 0 ) , , J N ( U P , t 0 , x 0 ) )  is called a Pareto maximum in the problem  Γ v .
Note two results, which are immediate from Definition 1.
Property 1.
[ J i ( U ^ , t 0 , x 0 ) > J i ( U P , t 0 , x 0 ) ] [ J j ( U ^ , t 0 , x 0 ) < J j ( U P , t 0 , x 0 ) ]
for at least one number  j , j i  and  U ^ U .
Property 2.
If the condition
max U U { i α i J i ( U , t 0 , x 0 ) } = I d e m { U U P }
holds for constants  α i > 0   ( i ) , then the alternative  U P  is Pareto-maximal in the problem  Γ v .  Here,  I d e m { U U P }  indicates the bracketed expression from (4) with replaced  U  by  U P .
Consider two concepts of equilibrium for the game Γ , where J = ( J 1 , , J N ) N .
Definition 2.
A pair  ( U e , J e = J ( U e , t 0 , x 0 ) ) U × N  is called a Nash equilibrium of the game  Γ  if
max U 1 U 1 J 1 ( U 1 , U 2 e , , U N e , t 0 , x 0 ) = J 1 ( U 1 e , U 2 e , , U N e , t 0 , x 0 ) = J 1 e , max U 2 U 2 J 2 ( U 1 e , U 2 , , U N e , t 0 , x 0 ) = J 2 ( U 1 e , U 2 e , , U N e , t 0 , x 0 ) = J 2 e , max U N U N J N ( U 1 e , U 2 e , , U N 1 e , U N , t 0 , x 0 ) = = J N ( U 1 e , , U N 1 e , U N e , t 0 , x 0 ) = J N e
for any  ( t 0 , x 0 ) [ 0 , ϑ ) × n , x 0 0 n  ( 0 n  denotes a zero vector of dimension n).
Now we construct the equilibrium in sanctions and countersanctions.
Let U = ( U 1 , U 2 , , U N ) be some fixed strategy profile of the game Γ . Player 1 is said to impose a sanction to the strategy profile U if there exists their strategy U 1 T U 1 such that
J 1 ( U 1 T , U 2 , , U N , t 0 , x 0 ) > J 1 ( U 1 , U 2 , , U N , t 0 , x 0 ) .
An existing sanction is not necessarily implemented: it means the threat of coercion. Recall that the role of a sanction is revealed through the legal responsibility of players: sanctions make them refrain from violating the established game rules and are implemented in case of “frustration”. In terms of game theory, implementing the sanction is beneficial to Player 1: according to (5), their individual payoff will increase compared to the previous strategy profile U .
The complex of punitive measures taken by one party against the other in response to sanctions is manifested in countersanctions. Player 2 is said to impose an incomplete countersanction to a sanction U 1 T of Player 1 if there exists a strategy U 2 C U 2 such that
J 1 ( U 1 T , U 2 C , , U N , t 0 , x 0 ) J 1 ( U 1 , U 2 , , U N , t 0 , x 0 ) .
Player 2 is said to impose a complete countersanction to U 1 T if there exists a strategy U 2 C U 2 such that Inequality (6) is satisfied simultaneously with
J 2 ( U 1 T , U 2 C , , U N , t 0 , x 0 ) > J 2 ( U 1 T , U 2 , , U N , t 0 , x 0 ) .
Incomplete and complete countersanctions of other players to a sanction U i T are formalized by analogy.
In the presence of an incomplete countersanction, Player 2 can choose their strategy U 2 C for making the payoff of Player 1 (who imposes an original sanction) equal to a value not exceeding their original payoff in the strategy profile U ; see (6). (Note that he (it) may even reduce the payoff of Player 1!) Therefore, the presence of an incomplete countersanction negates the implementation of a sanction. In addition, a complete countersanction motivates Player 2 to choose U 2 C because their payoff in the resulting strategy prole ( U 1 T , U 2 C , , U N ) yielded by implementing the sanction and countersanction will increase compared to the strategy prole ( U 1 T , U 2 , , U N ) yielded by implementing the sanction U 1 T . A sanction U i T of player i to a strategy profile U and a (complete) countersanction of one of the other players are defined by analogy.
If at least one of the other players has a countersanction to each sanction imposed by any player to U , then it makes no sense for him to implement the sanction: due to the countersanction of another player, their payoff will not increase (but it may even decrease!).
Definition 3.
A strategy profile  U P = ( U 1 P , U 2 P , , U N P ) U  is called an active equilibrium [13] of the game  Γ  if, for any initial position  ( t 0 , x 0 ) [ 0 , ϑ ) × n , x 0 0 n :
1. 
The alternative  U P  is Pareto-maximal in the N-criteria dynamic choice problem  Γ v .
2. 
At least one of the other players has an incomplete countersanction to each sanction  U i T U i  of any player.
Definition 4.
A pair  ( U P , J P ) U × N  is called an equilibrium in sanctions and countersanctions in the differential N-player game  Γ  if, for any initial position  ( t 0 , x 0 ) [ 0 , ϑ ) × n , x 0 0 n :
1. 
The alternative  U P  is Pareto-maximal in the N-criteria dynamic choice problem  Γ v .
2. 
At least one of the other players has an complete countersanction to each sanction  U i T U i  of any player.
As before, J P = ( J 1 P , J 2 P , , J N P ) and J i P = J i ( U P , t 0 , x 0 ) ( i ) . From Definitions 3 and 4, it follows that any equilibrium in sanctions and countersanctions is simultaneously an active equilibrium. Active equilibria and equilibria in sanctions and countersanctions are based on threats and counterthreats, well known in game theory [24]. They have all the positive properties of Nash equilibria [18]. More specifically:
  • They are stable against the deviations of an individual player.
  • They satisfy individual rationality.
  • They coincide with the saddle point in the case of zero-sum two-player games.
At the same time, these equilibria are free from the following disadvantages of Nash equilibrium [18]:
  • They exist in several cases when there is no Nash equilibrium (e.g., in the game Γ ).
  • Unlike Nash equilibrium, they are unimprovable and internally stable due to Pareto maximality.
  • The presence of a Nash equilibrium in the game implies the existence of certain types of unimprovable equilibria in which the payoffs of all players are no smaller than in the Nash equilibrium.
  • The best Nash equilibria (in the sense of Pareto maximality) are equilibria in sanctions and countersanctions.
Let us emphasize again: the requirement of efficiency (Pareto maximality) has been incorporated into Definitions 3 and 4 to eliminate some negative properties of Nash equilibrium, such as the internal and external instability of the set of Nash equilibria.
N.N. Krasovskii [40] formalized the concepts of players’ strategies and the motions of a dynamic system induced by them for a two-player zero-sum positional differential game. The constructions underlying the positive properties above are valid for a more general class––noncooperative positional differential games [41].
Note that under economic sanctions [42,43], the methodology for constructing active equilibria, particularly the concept of equilibrium in sanctions and countersanctions, is of utmost importance for economic–mathematical modeling of decision processes and applications.
Hereinafter, the notation D < 0 ( > 0 ) means that a quadratic form x D x is negative definite (positive definite, respectively).
Consider the auxiliary N-criteria static problem
Γ N = N n , { f i ( u ) = u 1 D i 1 u 1 + + u N D i N u N } i ,
in which the DM chooses an alternative u = ( u 1 , u 2 , , u N ) N n for simultaneously maximizing all components of a vector criterion f ( u ) = ( f 1 ( u ) , f 2 ( u ) , , f N ( u ) ) .
For this problem, Definition 1 can be reformulated as follows: an alternative u P is Pareto-maximal in Γ N if u N n the system of inequalities f i ( u ) f i ( u P ) ( i ) , with at least one strict inequality, is inconsistent.
We present some auxiliary properties of the quadratic forms x D x = γ , β = 1 n d γ β x γ x β with constant coefficients d γ β (the elements of a matrix D of dimensions n × n ) and the components x 1 , , x n of an n-dimensional vector x n .
Lemma 1.
With the change of coefficients  b γ β = d γ β + d β γ 2 , a quadratic form  x D x  is reduced to the form  x B x , where the matrix  B = ( b i j )  of dimensions  n × n  is symmetric, i.e.,  B = B .
Without loss of generality, all quadratic forms below are supposed to have symmetric matrices.
Lemma 2.
If  D i i > 0 , then all n roots of the characteristic equation  det [ D i i Λ E n ] = 0  are real and positive  ( i ) , where  E n  denotes an identity matrix of dimensions  n × n  [44].
Let Λ i i > 0 be the greatest root under consideration. Then
u i D i i u i Λ i i u i 2 = Λ i i u i u i u i n .
Since D > 0 D = ( 1 ) D < 0 , for D < 0 , all n roots λ i j < 0 of the characteristic equation det [ D i j λ E n ] = 0 are negative ( i , j , i j ) .
Let λ i j be the greatest (smallest by magnitude) root among them. By analogy with (9), we have
u j D i j u i λ i j u i u j u j n .
Without loss of generality, consider the N-criteria choice problem Γ N in which a sanction is imposed by Player 1 and a countersanction by Player 2. (The players are numbered subjectively).
The next result follows from Property 2.
Lemma 3.
Assume that in the problem  Γ N  :
1. The symmetric matrices  D i j   of dimensions  n × n  satisfy the inequalities  D i i > 0 , D i j < 0   ( i , j , i j )  and
Λ 11 Λ 22 < λ 12 λ 21 .
2. The nonzero matrix
A = Λ 11 λ 21 λ N 1 λ 12 Λ 22 λ N 2 λ 1 N λ 2 N Λ N N
of dimensions  N × N  is singular, i.e., its determinant is  det A = 0 .
Then, the system of strict homogeneous linear inequalities
+ α 1 Λ 11 α 2 λ 21 α 3 λ 31 α N λ N 1 < 0 , α 1 λ 12 + α 2 Λ 22 α 3 λ 32 α N λ N 2 < 0 , α 1 λ 13 α 2 λ 23 + α 3 Λ 33 α N λ N 3 < 0 , α 1 λ 1 N α 2 λ 2 N α 3 λ 3 N α N 1 λ N 1 N + α N Λ N N < 0 ,
has a positive solution  α = ( 1 , α 2 , , α N ) , α j > 0 , j = 2 , , N ,  where  Λ i i  and  λ i j ( i , j , i j )  are the greatest roots of the characteristic equations  det [ D i i Λ E n ] = 0  and  det [ D i j λ E n ] = 0 ,  respectively  ( i , j , i j ) .
Proof. 
To construct a Pareto-maximal strategy profile in the game Γ , we will apply Property 2 and the linear convolution i α i f i ( u ) of the criteria (8) with positive coefficients α i > 0 . For (8), we construct a quadratic form from the components of the Nn-dimensional vector u = ( u 1 , , u N ) :
f ( u ) = i α i f i ( u ) = i α i [ u 1 D i 1 u 1 + u 2 D i 2 u 2 + + u N D i N u N ] .
Due to (8)–(10),
f ( u ) = u 1 [ α 1 Λ 11 α 2 λ 21 α 3 λ 31 α N λ N 1 ] u 1 + + u 2 [ α 1 λ 12 + α 2 Λ 22 α 3 λ 32 α N λ N 2 ] u 2 + + + u N 1 [ α 1 λ 1 N 1 α 2 λ 2 N 1 + α N 1 Λ N 1 N 1 α N λ N N 1 ] u N 1 + + u N [ α 1 λ 1 N α 2 λ 2 N α N 1 λ N 1 N + α N Λ N N ] u N = = d 1 u 1 2 + + d N u N 2 .
The numbers α i = c o n s t > 0   ( i ) can be chosen so that all d i will become negative and
d 1 = [ α 1 Λ 11 α 2 λ 21 α 3 λ 31 α N λ N 1 ] , d 2 = [ α 1 λ 12 + α 2 Λ 22 α 3 λ 32 α N λ N 2 ] , d N 1 = [ α 1 λ 1 N 1 α 2 λ 2 N 1 + α N 1 Λ N 1 N 1 α N λ N N 1 ] , d N = [ α 1 λ 1 N α 2 λ 2 N α N 1 λ N 1 N + α N Λ N N ] .
To prove this fact, we associate with (12) the system of strict homogeneous linear inequalities
α 1 Λ 11 α 2 λ 21 < 0 , α 1 λ 12 + α 2 Λ 22 < 0 , α 1 λ 13 α 2 λ 23 + α 3 Λ 33 < 0 , α 1 λ 14 α 2 λ 24 α 3 λ 34 + α 4 Λ 44 < 0 , α 1 λ 1 N 1 α 2 λ 2 N 1 + α N 1 Λ N 1 N 1 < 0 , α 1 λ 1 N α 2 λ 2 N α N 1 λ N 1 N + α N Λ N N < 0 .
This system is obtained from (12) by discarding all negative terms, except for α 2 λ 21 in the first inequality and α 1 λ 12 in the second one. Adding negative terms only strengthens strict inequalities. Hence, for λ i j > 0 and α i > 0 , any positive solutions of System (14) are also positive for (12). Then, the quadratic form f ( u ) will be negative definite with respect to the Nn-dimensional vector u = ( u 1 , , u N ) if System (12) (or System (14)) has the positive solution α = ( 1 , α 1 , , α N ) ,   α γ > 0   ( γ = 2 , , N ) , that is, all numbers. Let us establish this result for System (14). To this end, we find α 2 from the first two strict inequalities of (14):
α 1 Λ 11 α 2 λ 21 < 0 , α 1 λ 12 + α 2 Λ 22 < 0 .
If α 1 = 1 , then for Λ i i > 0 and λ i j > 0   ( i , j , i j ) , there exists a positive number α 2 such that
Λ 11 α 2 λ 21 < 0 λ 12 + α 2 Λ 22 < 0 Λ 11 λ 21 < α 2 λ 12 Λ 22 > α 2 Λ 11 λ 21 < α 2 < λ 12 Λ 22 .
This inequality holds under Λ 11 Λ 22 < λ 12 λ 21 , e.g., for
α 2 = 1 2 Λ 11 λ 21 + λ 12 Λ 22 .
From the third inequality of (14), for α 1 = 1 and α 2 (15), we obtain
0 < α 3 < 1 Λ 33 λ 13 + λ 23 2 Λ 11 λ 21 + λ 12 Λ 22 ,
e.g., by letting α 3 = 1 2 Λ 33 λ 13 + λ 23 2 Λ 11 λ 31 + λ 32 Λ 22 . Continuing the considerations above, using the subsequent inequalities of (14) and the calculated values α 1 = 1 , α 2 , α 3 , , we finally arrive at the recurrent formula α N = 1 2 Λ N N [ λ 1 N + α 2 λ 2 N + + α N 1 λ N 1 N ] .
Remark 1.
By analogy with Lemma 3, we have the following result. Assume that in the problem  Γ N , the symmetric matrices  D i j  of dimensions  n × n  and positive numbers  Λ i i  and  λ i j  are such that  D i i > 0 , D i j < 0  for  i j  and  Λ 11 Λ 33 < Λ 13 Λ 31 .
Then, for
α 2 = 1 2 λ 13 Λ 33 + Λ 11 λ 31 , α 3 = 1 2 λ 12 Λ 22 + 1 2 λ 13 Λ 33 + Λ 11 λ 31 λ 32 Λ 22 ,
and  α γ ( γ = 4 , , N )  given by Lemma 3, the quadratic form
f ( u ) = f 1 ( u ) + α 2 f 2 ( u ) + α 3 f 3 ( u ) + + α N f N ( u ) = u 1 d 1 u 1 + u 2 d 2 u 2 + u 3 d 3 u 3 + + u N d N u N
becomes negative definite; the constants  d i < 0  are given by (13).
Really, α 2 and α 3 in this expression satisfy the strict inequalities (12).
Note that in addition to the solutions α γ (Lemma 3 and Remark 1), the system of strict inequalities (12) has a continuum of other solutions. As demonstrated below, each of them induces a specific equilibrium in sanctions and countersanctions of the differential game Γ under the conditions D i i > 0 , D i j < 0   ( i , j , i j ) .
Remark 2.
Positive solutions of (12) can be found using S.N. Chernikov’s approach [35]. To avoid cumbersome transformations and notations dictated by this approach, we propose an original method for proving Lemma 3.
Lemma 4.
The solutions  x ( t )  of the system  x ˙ = K ( t ) x ,   x ( t 0 ) = x 0 ,  where  K ( ) C n × n [ 0 , ϑ ] ,  satisfy the nontrivial property
x 0 0 n x ( t ) 0 n t [ t 0 , ϑ ] ;
here  0 n  denotes a zero vector from the space  n .
Proof. 
Assume on the contrary that t 1 ( t 0 , ϑ ] such that x ( t ) = 0 n . In other words, at the time instant t 1 , two different solutions of the system x ˙ = K ( t ) x are passing through the position ( t 1 , 0 n ) : the trivial one x ( 1 ) ( t ) = 0 n   t [ 0 , ϑ ] and the nontrivial one x ( 2 ) ( t ) induced by the nonzero initial condition x 0 0 n . This obviously contradicts the existence and uniqueness theorem for the solution of a matrix linear differential equation with continuous coefficients. □
Proposition 1.
Assume that in the differential game  Γ ,
D i i > 0 , D i j < 0 , C i < 0 ( i , j , i j )   and   Λ 11 Λ 22 < Λ 12 Λ 21 .
Then, a Pareto-maximal alternative  U P  in the N-criteria choice problem  Γ v  has the form
U P = ( U 1 P , U 2 P , , U N P ) ÷ ( u 1 P ( t , x ) , u 2 P ( t , x ) , , u N P ( t , x ) ) = = u P ( t , x ) = ( Q 1 P ( t ) x , Q 2 P ( t ) x , , Q N P ( t ) x ) = ( d 1 1 Θ P ( t ) x , d 2 1 Θ P ( t ) x , , d N 1 Θ P ( t ) x ) ,
where
Θ P ( t ) = [ X 1 ( t ) ] { C 1 + t ϑ X 1 ( τ ) [ d 1 1 + d 2 1 + + d N 1 ] [ X 1 ( τ ) ] d τ } 1 X 1 ( t )
is a continuous symmetric matrix of dimensions  n × n  on the time interval  [ 0 , ϑ ]  ; the negative constants  d i  are given by (13);
α 2 = 1 2 Λ 11 λ 21 + λ 12 Λ 22 , α 3 = 1 2 λ 13 Λ 33 + 1 2 Λ 12 λ 21 + λ 12 Λ 22 λ 23 Λ 33 ,
and the other numbers  α γ ( γ = 4 , , N )  are calculated by the recurrent formulas
α m = 1 2 Λ m m [ λ 1 m + α 2 λ 2 m + + α m 1 λ m 1 m ] ( m = 4 , , N ) ,
where  Λ i i  is the greatest root of the characteristic equation  det [ D i i Λ E n ] = 0   ( i ) ,  and  λ i j  is the greatest root of the characteristic equation  det [ D i j λ E n ] = 0   ( i , j , i j ) ;   E n  denotes an identity matrix of dimensions  n × n ; finally,  X ( t )  means the fundamental matrix of the system  x ˙ = A ( t ) x , X ( ϑ ) = E n .
Proof. 
We construct a Pareto-maximal alternative U P using Lemma 3 (formula (4)) and dynamic programming [16]. Due to Property 2, the application of dynamic programming reduces to two stages as follows.
First stage. For the problem Γ , find ( N 1 ) positive numbers α m ( m = 2 , , N 1 ) , a continuously differentiable scalar function V ( t , x ) = x Θ ( t ) x ,   Θ ( t ) = Θ ( t )   t [ 0 , ϑ ] , and Nn-dimensional vector functions u i ( t , x , V )   ( i ) such that
V ( ϑ , x ) = x C x , C = C 1 + α 2 C 2 + + α N C N , x n .
Then, using the scalar function
W ( t , x , u 1 , u 2 , , u N , V ) = V x + V t ( A ( t ) x + u 1 + u 2 + + u N ) + u 1 d 1 u 1 + u 2 d 2 u 2 + + u N d N u N ,
find Nn-dimensional vector functions u i ( t , x , V )   ( i ) from
max u 1 , u 2 , , u N W ( t , x , u 1 , u 2 , , u N , V ) = I d e m { u i u i ( t , x , V ) } ( i )
for any t [ 0 , ϑ ] , x n and V   V x = g r a d x V . The functions u i ( t , x , V ) in (22) exist under the following sufficient conditions: for all ( t , x ) [ 0 , ϑ ) × n ,
V x u ( t , x , V ) = V x + 2 d i u i ( t , x , V ) = 0 n , ( i ) , 2 W u i 2 = 2 d i E n < 0 , ( i ) ,
where (as before) 0 n denotes an n-dimensional zero vector from the space n , and d i < 0 by Lemma 3.
From (23), it follows that
u i ( t , x , V ) = 1 2 d 1 1 V x ( i ) .
Then
W ( t , x , u ( t , x , V ) , V ) = W [ t , x , V ] = V t + V x A ( t ) x 1 4 V x [ d 1 1 + d 2 1 + + d N 1 ] V x .
The second stage. Find the solution V = V P ( t , x ) = x Θ P x , Θ P = [ Θ P ( t ) ] , of the partial differential equation
W [ t , x , V ] = 0
with the boundary condition
V ( ϑ , x ) = x C x x n ,
where C = C 1 + α 2 C 2 + + α N C N . In other words, for all t [ 0 , ϑ ] and all x n ,
W [ t , x , V ( t , x ) ] = x Θ P x = 0 , V ( ϑ , x ) = x C x x n .
Consequently, the symmetric matrix Θ P ( t ) of dimensions n × n satisfies the Riccati matrix differential equation
Θ ˙ P ( t ) + Θ P ( t ) A ( t ) + A ( t ) Θ P ( t ) Θ P ( t ) [ d 1 1 + d 2 1 + + d N 1 ] Θ P ( t ) = 0 n × n , Θ P ( ϑ ) = C = C 1 + α 2 C 2 + + α N C N ,
where 0 n × n denotes a zero matrix of dimensions n × n .
As is well known [16], the solution Θ P ( t ) of the Riccati matrix differential equation has the form (18). (Here, the implication
C i < 0 ( i ) C 1 + α 2 C 2 + + α N C N < 0
has been taken into account). Formula (18), in combination with another implication
[ V ( t , x ) = x Θ P ( t ) x ] = V ( t , x ) x = 2 Θ P ( t ) x ,
finally yields (17). Thus, a Pareto-maximal alternative U P in the multicriteria choice problem Γ v is given by (17) and (18).
Now we construct the Pareto-maximal payoffs
J P = ( J 1 ( U P , t 0 , x 0 ) , J 2 ( U P , t 0 , x 0 ) , , J N ( U P , t 0 , x 0 ) ) = ( J 1 P , J 2 P , , J N P )
using dynamic programming and [44]. □
Proposition 2.
Let Conditions (16) of Proposition 1 be valid. Assume that for the differential game  Γ  , there are N scalar continuously differentiable functions  V i ( t , x ) = x Θ i ( t ) x ( i )  such that:
1. 
V i ( ϑ , x ) = x C i x x n ,
2. 
The system of N partial differential equations
V i t + V i x ( N ( t ) x + x Θ P ( t ) M i ( t ) Θ P ( t ) x ) = 0 , V i ( ϑ , x ) = x C i x , x n ( i )
has the solution  V i ( t , x ) = x Θ i ( t ) x ,   [ Θ i ( t ) ] = Θ i ( t ) ( i ) .
Then, for any initial position  ( t 0 , x 0 ) [ 0 , ϑ ) × n , x 0 0 n ,
J i P = J i ( U P , t 0 , x 0 ) = x 0 Θ i P ( t 0 ) x 0 ( i ) .
In (25),
N ( t ) = A ( t ) ( d 1 1 + d 2 1 + + d N 1 ) E n , M i ( t ) = Θ P ( t ) [ d 1 1 ] 2 D i 1 + [ d 2 1 ] 2 D i 2 + + [ d N 1 ] 2 D i N Θ P ( t ) ( i )
are continuous matrices of dimensions  n × n  ; the matrix  Θ P ( t )  is given by (17) and (18); the numbers  d i  are given by (13);
Θ i ( t ) = Y 1 ( t ) C i t ϑ Y ( τ ) Θ ( τ ) M i ( τ ) Y ( τ ) d τ Y 1 ( t )       ( i )
are symmetric matrices of dimensions  n × n ; finally,  Y ( t )  denotes the fundamental matrix of the homogeneous system  y ˙ = N ( t ) y , Y ( ϑ ) = E n .
Proof. 
We construct the N scalar functions
W [ t , x , V i ] = V t + V x ( N ( t ) x + [ u 1 P ( t , x ) ] D i 1 u 1 P ( t , x ) + + [ u 2 P ( t , x ) ] D i 2 u 2 P ( t , x ) + + [ u N P ( t , x ) ] D i N u N P ( t , x ) ( i ) ,
where u i P ( t , x ) are the n-dimensional vector functions given by (17) and (18).
Let us find the solution V i ( t , x )   ( i ) of the system of N partial differential equations
W i [ t , x , V i ] = 0 , V i ( ϑ , x ) = x C i x
as the quadratic form V i ( t , x ) = x Θ i ( t ) x , [ Θ i ( t ) ] = Θ i ( t )   ( i ) .
We will establish two facts as follows.
First, the solution of Systems (27) and (28) has the property
V i ( t 0 , x 0 ) = J i ( U P , t 0 , x 0 ) ( i ) ,
where the strategy profile U P = ( U 1 P , U 2 P , , U N P ) has the form (17) and (18). Really, if U P is a strategy profile from (12)–(14), then by (27) and (28), the solution x P ( t ) of the system x ˙ = N ( t ) x ,   x ( t 0 ) = x 0 0 n , for x = x P ( t ) will be
0 = W i [ t , x p ( t ) , V i ( t , x p ( t ) ) ] = = V i ( t , x p ( t ) ) t + V i ( t , x p ( t ) ) x N ( t ) x p ( t ) + j = 1 N [ u j P ( t , x P ( t ) ) ] D i j u j P ( t , x P ( t ) ) = W ¯ i [ t ] t [ t 0 ϑ ] ( i ) .
Integrating both sides of this identity from t 0 to ϑ subject to the boundary conditions (28) yields
0 = t 0 ϑ W ¯ i [ t ] d t = t 0 ϑ d V i ( t , x P ( t ) ) d t d t + t 0 ϑ j = 1 N [ u j P ( t , x P ( t ) ) ] D i j u j P ( t , x P ( t ) ) d t = = V i P ( ϑ , x P ( ϑ ) ) V i P ( t 0 , x P ( t 0 ) ) + t 0 ϑ j = 1 N [ u j P ( t , x P ( t ) ) ] D i j u j P ( t , x P ( t ) ) d t = = x ( ϑ ) C i x ( ϑ ) + t 0 ϑ j = 1 N [ u j P ( t , x P ( t ) ) ] D i j u j P ( t , x P ( t ) ) d t V i P ( t 0 , x P ( t 0 ) ) = = J i ( U P , t 0 , x 0 ) V i P ( t 0 , x P ( t 0 ) ) ( i ) .
Hence, Property (29) is proved.
Second, the solution of System (29) has the form V i ( t , x ) = x Θ i ( t ) x , where a symmetric matrix Θ i ( t ) of dimensions n × n is given by (26). Really, substituting V i ( t , x ) = x Θ i ( t ) x into (28) leads to (29) if Θ i ( t ) is the solution of the matrix linear inhomogeneous differential equation
Θ i + Θ i N + N Θ i + Θ P ( t ) M i Θ P ( t ) = 0 n × n , Θ P ( ϑ ) = C i ( i ) .
A direct substitution of (26) into equation (29) shows that this symmetric matrix Θ i ( t ) of dimensions n × n is the desired solution. The proof of Proposition 2 is complete.
Note that
d Y 1 ( t ) d t = Y 1 ( t ) A ( t ) , d [ Y 1 ( t ) ] d t = A ( t ) [ Y 1 ( t ) ] .
Remark 3.
Propositions 1 and 2 considered together finally yield the following explicit form of the Pareto-maximal solution  ( U P , J P ) U × n  of the game  Γ .
Assume that in the differential game  Γ :
1. 
The symmetric constant matrices  D i j  and  C i  of dimensions  n × n  are such that
D i i > 0 , D i j < 0 , C i < 0 ( i , j , i j ) .
2. 
Λ 11 Λ 22 < λ 12 λ 21 .
Then, for all  ( t 0 , x 0 ) [ 0 , ϑ ) × n , x 0 0 n ,
U P ÷ u P ( t , x ) = ( d 1 1 Θ P ( t ) x , d 2 1 Θ P ( t ) x , , d N 1 Θ P ( t ) x ) , J P = ( J 1 P , J 2 P , , J N P ) , ( J i P = x 0 Θ i ( t 0 ) x 0 ( i ) ,
where
Θ P ( t ) = [ X 1 ( t ) ] C 1 + t ϑ X 1 ( τ ) [ d 1 1 + d 2 1 + + d N 1 ] [ X 1 ( τ ) ] d τ 1 X 1 ( t ) , Θ i ( t ) = [ Y 1 ( t ) ] C i t ϑ Y ( τ ) Θ P M i ( τ ) Θ P Y ( τ ) d τ Y 1 ( t ) ,
are symmetric matrices of dimensions  n × n  ; the matrices  X ( t )  and  Y ( t )  of dimensions  n × n  are the fundamental matrices of the systems  x ˙ = A ( t ) x ,   X ( ϑ ) = E n  and  y ˙ = N ( t ) x ,   Y ( ϑ ) = E n respectively;
C = C 1 + α 2 C 2 + + α N C N , N ( t ) = A ( t ) ( d 1 1 + d 2 1 + + d N 1 ) Θ P ( t ) , M i ( t ) = Θ P ( t ) [ d 1 1 ] 2 D i 1 + [ d 2 1 ] 2 D i 2 + + [ d N 1 ] 2 D i N Θ P ( t ) ,
the numbers  α 2 = 1 2 λ 13 Λ 33 + Λ 11 λ 31 ,   α 3 = 1 2 λ 12 Λ 22 + 1 2 λ 13 Λ 33 + Λ 11 λ 31 λ 32 Λ 22 , ,  and  α γ ( γ = 4 , N )  are given by (20); the negative numbers  d i  are given by (13);  Λ i j  and  λ i j  are the greatest roots of the characteristic equations  det [ D i i Λ E n ] = 0  and  det [ D i j λ E n ] = 0 , respectively  ( i , j , i j ) .
  • Lemmas of Majorants
Next, let us proceed to the propositions that
  • Will allow us to reveal the absence of Nash equilibrium in differential games if (11) is satisfied;
  • Realize for the game the concept of sanctions and countersanctions for the differential game Γ.
These items (1) and (2) involve the definiteness of quadratic forms figuring in the integral terms of the payoff functions (3). From this point onwards, assume that Conditions (11) are satisfied. Hence, there exists a Pareto-maximal alternative
U P = ( U 1 P , U 2 P , , U N P ) ÷ ( u 1 P ( t , x ) , u 2 P ( t , x ) , , u N P ( t , x ) ) = = u P ( t , x ) = ( Q 1 P ( t ) x , Q 2 P ( t ) x , , Q N P ( t ) x ) = = ( d 1 1 Θ P ( t ) x , d 2 1 Θ P ( t ) x , , d N 1 Θ P ( t ) x ) .
in the N-criteria choice problem Γ v .
Lemma 5.
Let the payoff function (3) be such that  D 11 > 0 . Then, for a Pareto-maximal strategy profile alternative  U P  in the game  Γ ,  there exists a constant  α ( 1 ) ( U P , t 0 , x 0 ) > 0  such that, for all  α = α ( 1 ) ( U P , t 0 , x 0 ) > 0  and the strategy  U 1 T ÷ α x  of Player 1, the inequality
J 1 ( U 1 T , U 2 P , , U N P , t 0 , x 0 ) > J 1 ( U 1 P , U 2 P , , U N P , t 0 , x 0 )
will hold for any initial positions  ( t 0 , x 0 ) [ 0 , ϑ ) × [ n \ { 0 n } ] .
Proof. 
According to Proposition 2, there exists a Bellman function V 1 ( t , x ) = x Θ 1 ( t ) x such that
J 1 ( U P , t 0 , x 0 ) = V 1 ( t 0 , x 0 ) = x 0 Θ 1 ( t 0 ) x 0 ,
where the symmetric matrix Θ 1 ( t ) of dimensions n × n is continuous on [ 0 , ϑ ) and has the form (26) ( i = 1 ) .
Consider the strategy U 1 T ÷ u 1 T ( t , x ) = α x of Player 1, in which the numerical parameter α > 0 will be determined below. Due to the symmetry of the matrix D 11 and D 11 > 0 ,
u 1 D 11 u 1 λ 1 u 1 2 = λ 1 u 1 u 1 u 1 n ,
where · denotes the Euclidean norm, and λ 1 > 0 is the smallest root of the characteristic equation det [ D 11 λ E n ] ; see [45].
We take the symmetric matrix Θ P ( t ) of dimensions n × n from (18) and the strategies U 2 P ÷ Q 2 P ( t ) x , , U N P ÷ Q N P ( t ) x of players 2 , , N , respectively, from (17). We introduce the scalar function
W 1 [ t , x ] = = [ W 1 ( t , x , u 1 T ( t , x ) = α x , u 2 T ( t , x ) = Q 2 P x , , u N T ( t , x ) = Q N P x , V ( t , x ) 1 = x Θ 1 ( t ) x ] = = V 1 ( t , x ) t + V 1 ( t , x ) x ( A ( t ) x + u 1 T ( t , x ) + u 2 T ( t , x ) + + u N T ( t , x ) ) + + [ u 1 T ( t , x ) ] d 1 u 1 T ( t , x ) + [ u 2 T ( t , x ) ] d 2 u 2 T ( t , x ) + + [ u N T ( t , x ) ] d N u N T ( t , x ) x d Θ 1 ( t ) d t x + 2 x Θ 1 ( t ) [ A ( t ) + α E n + Q 2 P ( t ) + Q N P ( t ) ] x + + x ( λ 1 α 2 E n ) x + x [ Q 2 P ( t ) ] D 12 Q 2 P ( t ) x + + x [ Q N P ( t ) ] D 1 N Q N P ( t ) x = x { d Θ 1 ( t ) d t + Θ 1 ( t ) [ A ( t ) + α E n + Q 2 P ( t ) + + Q N P ( t ) ] + + [ A ( t ) + α E n + ( Q 2 P ( t ) ) + + ( Q N P ( t ) ) ] Θ 1 ( t ) + λ 1 α 2 E n + + [ Q 2 P ( t ) ] D 12 Q 2 P ( t ) + + [ Q N P ( t ) ] D 1 N Q N P ( t ) } x = = x M 1 ( t , α ) x .
The matrix M 1 ( t , α ) in curly brackets is symmetric and has the form
M 1 ( t , α ) = λ 1 α 2 E n + 2 α Θ 1 ( t ) + K 1 ( t ) ,
where
K 1 ( t ) = Θ ˙ 1 ( t ) + Θ 1 ( t ) [ A ( t ) + Q 2 P ( t ) + + Q N P ( t ) ] + [ Q 2 P ( t ) ] D 12 Q 2 P ( t ) + + [ Q N P ( t ) ] D 1 N Q N P ( t ) + + [ A ( t ) + ( Q 2 P ( t ) ) + + ( Q N P ( t ) ) ] Θ 1 ( t )
is a symmetric and continuous matrix of dimensions n × n .
The elements of the matrices Θ 1 ( t ) and K 1 ( t ) are continuous on [ 0 , ϑ ] and hence uniformly bounded on the compact set [ 0 , ϑ ] . The factor α 2 enters only the diagonal elements of the matrix M 1 ( t , α ) . Recall that λ 1 > 0 is the smallest root of the characteristic equation det [ D 11 λ E n ] = 0 , where E n denotes an identity matrix of dimensions n × n . Therefore, the constant α = α ( 1 ) ( U P , t 0 , x 0 ) > 0 can be chosen sufficiently great for making all principal minors of the matrix M 1 ( t , α ) positive t [ 0 , ϑ ]   α α ( 1 ) ( U P , t 0 , x 0 ) . (This fact will be proved below). According to Lemma 2 and [46], the quadratic form x M 1 ( t , α ) x is positive definite for all t [ 0 , ϑ ] and all constants α α ( 1 ) ( U P , t 0 , x 0 ) .
Now we show the existence of a constant α ( 1 ) ( U P , t 0 , x 0 ) > 0 such that, for all α α ( 1 ) ( U P , t 0 , x 0 ) , the quadratic form x M 1 ( t , α ) x is positive definite for all t [ 0 , ϑ ] and x n . Note that the matrix M 1 ( t , α ) of dimensions n × n is symmetric. By Sylvester’s criterion, the quadratic form x M 1 ( t , α ) x is positive definite if all principal minors Δ r ( r = 1 , , n ) of the matrix M 1 ( t , α ) are positive. The minors Δ r are located in the first r rows and first r columns of the matrix M 1 ( t , α )   ( r = 1 , , n ) :
Δ r ( t , α ) = λ 1 α 2 n + α l 11 ( t ) + k 11 ( t ) α l 1 r ( t ) + k 1 r ( t ) α l r 1 ( t ) + k r 1 ( t ) λ 1 α 2 n + α l r r ( t ) + k r r ( t ) .
They must be positive t [ 0 , ϑ ] and α α ( 1 ) ( U P , t 0 , x 0 ) . Expanding the determinants Δ r ( t , α ) and rearranging the terms in the descending order of the power of the parameter α , we obtain
Δ r ( t , α ) = α 0 ( t ) α 2 r + α 1 ( t ) α 2 r 1 + + α 2 r 1 ( t ) α + α 2 r ( t ) ,
where α 0 = λ r n r > 0 (constant), and the other coefficients α 1 ( t ) , , α 2 r ( t ) are continuous on the compact set [ 0 , ϑ ] , hence being uniformly bounded. This uniform boundedness guarantees the existence of Ω r = c o n s t > 0 such that
max 0 t ϑ { α p ( t ) p = 0 , 1 , , 2 r } < Ω r .
Let us demonstrate that if
α > Ω r α 0 + 1 = α ( 1 ) ( U P , t 0 , x 0 ) ,
then
α 1 ( t ) α 2 r 1 + α 2 ( t ) α 2 r 2 + + α 2 r 1 ( t ) α + α 2 r ( t ) < α 0 α 2 r .
In other words, for a sufficiently great value α , the sign of the polynomial Δ r ( t , α ) is determined by the sign of its leading term. Really,
α 1 ( t ) α 2 r 1 + α 2 ( t ) α 2 r 2 + + α 2 r 1 ( t ) α + α 2 r ( t ) α 1 ( t ) α 2 r 1 + α 2 ( t ) α 2 r 2 + + α 2 r 1 ( t ) α + α 2 r ( t ) Ω r ( α 2 r 1 + α 2 r 2 + + α + 1 ) = Ω r α 2 r 1 α 1 .
In addition,
α > Ω r α 0 + 1 [ Ω r < α 0 ( α 1 ) ] .
Replacing Ω r in this inequality by a greater value α 0 ( α 1 ) yields
α 1 ( t ) α 2 r 1 + α 2 ( t ) α 2 r 2 + + α 2 r 1 ( t ) α + α 2 r ( t ) < < α 0 ( α 1 ) α 2 r 1 α 1 = α 0 ( α 1 ) < α 0 α 2 r .
Thus α Ω r = α ( r ) ( U , t 0 , x 0 ) > 0 , and t [ 0 , ϑ ] , we have
α 1 ( t ) α 2 r 1 + α 2 ( t ) α 2 r 2 + + α 2 r 1 ( t ) α + α 2 r ( t ) < α 0 α 2 r .
Well, for a sufficiently great value α , the sign of the polynomial Δ r ( t , α ) is determined by the sign of its leading term. Finally, for each r = 1 , , n , we calculate Ω r > 0 and let α ( 1 ) ( U P , t 0 , x 0 ) = max r = 1 , , n Ω r .
Then, for α ( 1 ) ( U P , t 0 , x 0 ) , it follows that
W ˜ 1 [ t , x ] = x M 1 ( t , α ( 1 ) ) x > 0 t [ 0 , ϑ ] x n \ { 0 n } .
We denote by x ˜ ( t ) , t [ 0 , ϑ ] , the solution of the vector differential equation
x ˙ = A ( t ) x + α ( 1 ) x + Q 2 P ( t ) x + + Q N P ( t ) x , x ( t 0 ) = x 0 0 n .
Due to Lemma 2, the implication [ x 0 0 n ] ( x ˜ ( t ) 0 n   t [ 0 , ϑ ] ) and (32),
W ˜ 1 [ t , x ˜ ( t ) ] > 0 , t [ 0 , ϑ ] .
Integrating both sides of (32) from t 0 to ϑ subject to the boundary condition Θ 1 ( ϑ ) = C 1 and u 1 T [ t ] = α ( 1 ) x ˜ ( t ) gives:
0 = t 0 ϑ W ˜ 1 [ t , x ˜ ( t ) ] d t = = t 0 ϑ V 1 ( t , x ) t + V 1 ( t , x ) x [ A [ t ] x + α ( 1 ) E n x + Q 2 P ( t ) x + + Q N P ( t ) x ] x = x ˜ ( t ) d t = = t 0 ϑ { ( α ( 1 ) ) 2 x D 11 x + x [ Q 2 P ( t ) ] D 12 Q 2 P ( t ) + + x [ Q N P ( t ) ] D 1 N Q N P ( t ) } x = x ˜ ( t ) d t = = t 0 ϑ d V 1 ( t , x ˜ ( t ) ) d t + t 0 ϑ j = 1 N [ u j T [ t ] ] D 1 j u j T [ t ] d t = = [ x ˜ ( ϑ ) ] C 1 x ˜ ( ϑ ) + t 0 ϑ j = 1 N [ u j T [ t ] ] D 1 j u j T [ t ] d t V 1 ( t 0 , x 0 ) = = J 1 ( U 1 T , U 2 P , , U N P , t 0 , x 0 ) V 1 ( t 0 , x 0 ) .
This result, in combination with the equality J 1 ( U 1 P , U 2 P , , U N P , t 0 , x 0 ) = V 1 ( t 0 , x 0 ) , finally proves Lemma 5. □
Remark 4.
Consider the inner optimization problem in the game  Γ : for fixed strategies  U 2 = U 2 P U 2 , , U N = U N P U N  of players  2 , , N , respectively, and for any  ( t 0 , x 0 ) [ 0 , ϑ ) × [ n \ { 0 n } ] , find  max U 1 U 1 J 1 ( U 1 , U 2 P , , U N P , t 0 , x 0 )  subject to System (1). Lemma 5 claims that for  D 11 > 0  and  x 0 0 n , this problem maximization problem has no solution. Really, whatever strategy  U 1 U 1  is chosen by Player 1, there always exists another strategy  U 1 T  of this player such that
J 1 ( U ˜ 1 T , U 2 P , , U N P , t 0 , x 0 ) > J 1 ( U 1 , U 2 P , , U N P , t 0 , x 0 ) ( t 0 , x 0 ) [ 0 , ϑ ) × [ n \ { 0 n } ] .
When choosing an appropriate solution of the game  Γ  , this result allows directly eliminating those concepts of equilibrium that involve the maximization of the payoff function of Player 1 with respect to  U 1 .  (For example, if  D 11 > 0  , the concept of Nash equilibrium should not be used as the solution of the game  Γ  ).
Thus, under Conditions (11), the differential game  Γ  has no Nash equilibrium. At the same time, the strategy  U 1 T ÷ α x α α ( 1 ) ( U P , t 0 , x 0 )  implements the sanction of Player 1 to the Pareto-maximal (efficient) strategy profile  U P  ; see (5). In the lemmas below, the initial position  ( t 0 , x 0 )  is fixed and coincides with the one from Lemma 5; in addition, the sanction strategy  U 1 T ÷ α x  of Player 1 has a constant scalar  α = α ( 1 )  . Recall that Conditions (11) are assumed to hold without special mention. Well, Lemma 5 establishes the following result.
Proposition 3.
Assume that in the game  Γ , at least one of the constant symmetric matrices  D i i > 0   ( i )  of dimensions  n × n  is positive definite. Then, this game has no Nash equilibrium, i.e., there does not exist a strategy  U i e U i  satisfying Definition 2.
Note that:
1. 
The condition  D i i > 0  with a fixed number  i  breaks only the i th equality of Definition 2. This is enough for the absence of a Nash equilibrium  U e  in the game  Γ  . If  D i i > 0  for all  i  , then the N equalities of Definition 2 will be violated.
2. 
The equivalence
D > 0 D < 0
is obvious. (Here,—D means that all elements of the matrix D are multiplied by –1).
Then, Lemma 5 also implies the following.
Lemma 6.
Let the payoff function (3) be such that  D 12 > 0 . Then, there exists a constant  α ( 2 ) = α ( 2 ) ( U P , U 1 T , t 0 , x 0 ) > 0  such that, for all  α α ( 2 )  and the strategy  U 2 C ÷ α x  of Player 2,
J 1 ( U 1 T , U 2 C , U 3 P , , U N P , t 0 , x 0 ) < J 1 ( U P , t 0 , x 0 ) .
In other words, the strategy  U 2 C ÷ α x α α ( 2 )  implements in the game  Γ  an incomplete countersanction to the sanction  U 1 T  of Player 1.
Proof. 
With some obvious modifications, the proof is immediate from Lemma 5.
Let a Bellman function V ˜ 1 ( t , x ) = x Θ ˜ ( t ) x ,   Θ ˜ ( t ) = Θ 1 ( t ) , be constructed, satisfying
J 1 ( U 1 T , U 2 P , , U N P , t 0 , x 0 ) = V ˜ 1 ( t 0 , x 0 ) .
By analogy with Lemmas 5 and 6, we will establish another important result below. Recall that an initial position ( t 0 , x 0 ) , a continuous matrix Θ P ( t ) of dimensions n × n , and an incomplete countersanction strategy U 2 C ÷ α ( 2 ) x figuring in Lemmas 5 and 6 are assumed to be fixed, and Conditions (11) are assumed to hold. □
Lemma 7.
The condition  D 22 > 0  implies the existence of a value  α ( 3 ) ( U P , U 1 T , t 0 , x 0 ) = c o n s t > 0  such that, for all  α > α ( 3 )  and the strategy  U 2 C ÷ α x ,
J 2 ( U 1 T , U 2 C , U 3 P , t 0 , x 0 ) < J 2 ( U 1 T , U 2 P , U 3 P , t 0 , x 0 ) .
In other words, the strategy  U 2 C ÷ ( max { α ( 2 ) , α ( 3 ) } ) x  of Player 2 implements a complete countersanction, jointly with  U 2 C ÷ α ( 2 ) x , to the sanction of Player 1 to  U P .
The sanctions of another player and countersanctions of the other players are constructed similarly.
  • Proof of Existence
Theorem 1.
Assume that the game  Γ = , Σ ÷ ( 2 ) , { U i } i , { J i ( U , t 0 , x 0 ) ÷ ( 3 ) } i  satisfies Conditions (16). Then, the (N + 1)-tuple
( U P , J 1 P , J 2 P , , J N P ) = ( ( U 1 P , U 2 P , , U N P ) , J 1 ( U P , t 0 , x 0 ) , J 2 ( U P , t 0 , x 0 ) , , J N ( U P , t 0 , x 0 ) = ( ( d 1 1 Θ P ( t ) x , d 2 1 Θ P ( t ) x , , d N 1 Θ P ( t ) x ) , x 0 Θ 1 ( t 0 ) x 0 , x 0 Θ 2 ( t 0 ) x 0 , , x 0 Θ N ( t 0 ) x 0 )
is an equilibrium in sanctions and countersanctions of differential game  Γ  where:
Θ P ( t ) = [ X 1 ( t ) ] { C 1 t ϑ X 1 ( τ ) [ d 1 1 + d 2 1 + + d N 1 ] [ X 1 ( τ ) ] d t } 1 X 1 ( t ) ;
the constants  d i  are given by (13);  C = C 1 + α 2 C 2 + + α N C N ,  where  α 2 = 1 2 Λ 11 λ 21 + λ 12 Λ 22 ,   α 3 = 1 2 Λ 13 λ 33 + 1 2 Λ 11 λ 21 + λ 12 Λ 22 λ 23 Λ 33  and  α m = 1 2 Λ m n [ λ 1 m + α 2 λ 2 m + + α m 1 λ m 1 m ]   ( m = 4 , , N )  and  Λ i  and  λ i j  are the smallest and greatest roots of the equations  det [ D i j Λ E n ] = 0  and  det [ D i j λ E n ] = 0 , respectively;  X ( t )  denotes the fundamental matrix of the system  x ˙ = A ( t ) x ,   X ( ϑ ) = E n   ( i , j , i j ) ; finally, the symmetric matrices  Θ i ( t ) ( i )  are given by (26).
Proof. 
The absence of a Nash equilibrium in the game Γ and the presence of a sanction U 1 T imposed by Player 1 to a Pareto-maximal alternative U P in the N-criteria choice problem Γ v immediately follow from D 11 > 0 ; see Remark 4. The existence of a Pareto-maximal alternative and Pareto-maximal outcomes in Γ v (including their explicit forms in this case) has been established by Propositions 2 and 3, respectively. The condition D 21 > 0 allows constructing an incomplete countersanction U 2 C of Player 2 to the sanctions of Player 1 (Lemma 6). The condition D 22 > 0 and Lemma 7 enable transforming the incomplete countersanction U 2 C of Player 2 into the complete one U 2 C . The requirement D 22 > 0 simultaneously implies the absence of a Nash equilibrium ( max U 1 J ( U 1 , U 2 e , U 3 e , , U N e , t 0 , x 0 ) is not achieved U ¯ 1 C U 1 ) and the ability of Player 2 to design analytically a sanction U 2 T to U P in the game Γ :
J 2 ( U 1 C , U 2 T , U 3 P , , U N P ) J 2 ( U P t 0 , x 0 ) .
The condition D 22 > 0 and Lemma 7 guarantee the existence of an incomplete countersanction U ¯ 1 C U 1 of Player 1 to the sanction U 2 T of Player 2:
J 2 ( U 1 C , U 2 T , U 3 P , , U N P ) < J 2 ( U P t 0 , x 0 ) .
Finally, the Pareto maximality of U P and Property 1 lead to
J 1 ( U 1 P , U 2 T , U 3 P , , U N P ) < J 1 ( U P t 0 , x 0 ) .
Due to D 11 > 0 and Lemma 5, there exists a U ¯ 1 C U 1 such that
J 1 ( U ¯ 1 C , U 2 T , U 3 P , , U N P ) > J 1 ( U 1 P , U 2 T , U 3 P , , U N P , t 0 , x 0 ) .
The countersanction to the sanctions imposed by players 3 , , N to U P is designed by analogy.
Thus, one of the other players in the game Γ always has a complete countersanction to a sanction imposed by any player to the Pareto-maximal strategy profile U P . The proof of Theorem 1 is complete. □

4. Discussion

Game-theoretic analysis of international legal agreements is based on a qualitative assessment of the interaction mechanisms between their participants. The application of this methodology is also justified by the fact that, unlike national law, international law lacks a superstructure with the legal personality to punish violations of these agreements and to compel the participants to fulfill them. As a rule, the subjects of international law agree with each other on the mechanisms of fulfilling legal prescriptions and responsibility for their violations. However, recently the system of international law is undergoing significant changes, which changes the basis of relations between its subjects and, accordingly, some consequences affect the functioning of national socio-economic systems. At the same time, the application of sanctioning legal regimes concerning individual national economies becomes a demanded multilateral mechanism of economic and political coercion. The so-called “treaty games” are often used to analyze the parties’ benefits and the effectiveness of existing and planned international legal regimes. They make it possible to estimate the number of sanctions and compensatory payments to ensure that the signing (implementation) of an agreement benefits all parties and prevents the violation of international legal regimes. As a rule, classical symmetric games with nonzero sums are widely used to model situations arising during the creation and modification of international legal regimes.
In contrast to such studies [47,48,49,50,51,52,53,54,55,56,57,58], this article presents a new methodology for modeling decision-making processes in complex controlled dynamic systems and forms a mechanism of equilibrium of sanctions and countersanctions, which contributes to solving the problems of stability of equilibria: a linear-quadratic positional differential game of many individuals is considered, coefficient criteria are established if they are met, there is an equilibrium of sanctions and countersanctions in the game, and there is no generally accepted Nash equilibrium.
The substantive meaning of the result obtained in this study is as follows. Both for the subjects using sanction coercive regimes and for the subjects stabilizing the situation by countersanctions, under certain conditions, there is a situation of stable effective active equilibrium with the most tremendous benefits for its participants. Thus, a debatable question is raised: If there is a way to use sanctions for one’s benefit, how expedient is their use?

5. Conclusions

This research demonstrates that there is no Nash equilibrium in a linear-quadratic game when Constraints (11) are satisfied. However, there is an equilibrium of sanctions and countersanctions. The novelty of the study of the theory of differential games is that
The equilibrium of sanctions and countersanctions is simultaneously Pareto-maximal;
A wide sufficient class of differential games of N persons at N 2 , in which there is an equilibrium of sanctions and countersanctions and simultaneously there is no Nash equilibrium;
An algorithm for practical constructing the equilibrium of sanctions and countersanctions is proposed.
The research results allow us to assert that the economic and legal justification of the construction of game-theoretic equilibrium models expands the practical application of the class of problems considered in this paper. At the same time, the authors do not claim the universality of game-theoretic methodology in modeling socio-economic processes. At the same time, they show the urgent need for additional research into the properties used in the analytical construction of various equilibria, including the equilibrium of sanctions and countersanctions, as a mechanism for researching the equilibrium of complex controlled systems.

Author Contributions

Conceptualization, V.I.Z. and L.V.Z.; methodology, V.I.Z. and L.V.Z.; formal analysis, V.I.Z.; investigation, L.V.Z. All authors have read and agreed to the published version of the manuscript.

Funding

This research received no external funding.

Data Availability Statement

The authors declare no conflict of interest.

Conflicts of Interest

The authors declare no conflict of interest. The funders had no role in the design of the study; in the collection, analyses, or interpretation of data; in the writing of the manuscript; or in the decision to publish the results.

References

  1. Prostoserdov, M.A. Game-Theoretic Approach to the Formation of a System of Sanctions in the Criminal Legislation of the Russian Federation. Ross. Pravosud. 2022, 172–186. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  2. Tsebelis, G. Are Sanctions Effective? A Game-Theoretic Analysis. J. Confl. Resolut. 1990, 34, 3–28. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  3. Jentleson, B. Historical Perspective: Lessons from Past Sanctions Cases Lessons from Past Sanctions Cases; Oxford University Press: Oxford, UK, 2023. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  4. Jeong, J. Sanctions-Busting, Material Power, and Institutional Support for Economic Sanctions. J. Confl. Resolut. 2023, 002200272311544. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  5. Afesorgbor, S.K. The impact of economic sanctions on international trade: How do threatened sanctions compare with imposed sanctions? Eur. J. Political Econ. 2019, 56, 11–26. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  6. Walentek, D. Reputation or Interaction: What Determines Cooperation on Economic Sanctions? Int. Interact. 2022, 48, 1121–1143. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  7. Simon, M.V. When Sanctions can work: Economic sanctions and the theory of moves. Int. Interact. 1995, 21, 203–228. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  8. Shadiqi, K.; Pradiptyo, R. A Game Theoretical Analysis of Economic Sanctions; Munich Personal RePEc Archive: Munich, Germany, 2011; Available online: https://mpra.ub.uni-muenchen.de/30481/ (accessed on 12 March 2023).
  9. Karimi, M.S.; Maleki, A.; Haieri Yazdi, A. How the possibility of a fight-back strategy affects the consequences of a sanction’s regime. J. Int. Stud. 2020, 13, 264–279. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  10. Onder, M. The Impact of Decision-Makers on Economic Sanctions: A Game Theoretical Perspective. Mich. Acad. 2021, 47, 89. [Google Scholar]
  11. Zhukovskaya, L.V. Balancing Economic, Legal, and Social Macrosystems Based on Modelling Decision Processes; Nova Science Publishers, Inc.: Hauppauge, NY, USA, 2022; p. 231. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  12. Zhukovskiy, V.I.; Kudryavtsev, K.N.; Samsonov, S.P.; Vysokov, M.I.; Belskikh, Y.A. A Class of Differential Games in Which Nash Equilibrium is Absent but There Exists a Berge Equilibrium. Vestn. South Ural. State Univ. Ser. Math. Mech. Phys. 2018, 10, 5–21. [Google Scholar]
  13. Smolyakov, E.R. Theory of Conflict Equilibria; URSS: Moscow, Russia, 2005. [Google Scholar]
  14. Kleiner, G.B.; Rybachuk, M.A. The Systemic Balancedness of Economy; Central Mathematics and Economics Institute, Russian Academy of Sciences: Moscow, Russia, 2017. [Google Scholar]
  15. Zhukovskaya, L.V. The Balancedness of the Social, Economic, and Legal Macrosystems Based on Modelling Decision Processes. Ph.D. Thesis, Federal Research Center “Computer Science and Control”, the Russian Academy of Sciences, Moscow, Russia, 2020. [Google Scholar]
  16. Zhukovskiy, V.I.; Chikrii, A.A. Differential Equations. Linear-Quadratic Differential Games; Yurait: Moscow, Russia, 2017. [Google Scholar]
  17. Zhukovskiy, V.I.; Tynyanskiy, N.T. Equilibrium Controls of Multicriteria Dynamic Problems; Krasand: Moscow, Russia, 2010. [Google Scholar]
  18. Zhukovskiy, V.I. An Introduction to Differential Games under Uncertainty. The Equilibrium in Threats and Counterthreats, 2nd ed.; Krasand: Moscow, Russia, 2010. [Google Scholar]
  19. Nash, J.F. Equilibrium Points in N-Person Games. Proc. Nat. Acad. Sci. USA 1950, 36, 48–49. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  20. Nash, J.F. The Bargaining Problem. Econometrica 1950, 18, 155–162. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  21. Nash, J.F. Non-Cooperative Games. Ann. Math. 1951, 54, 286–295. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  22. Nash, J.F. Two Person Cooperative Games. Econometrica 1953, 21, 128–140. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  23. Luce, R.D.; Raiffa, H. Games and Decisions: Introduction and Critical Survey; Dover Publications: New York, NY, USA, 1957. [Google Scholar]
  24. Owen, G. Game Theory; Saunders: Bingley, UK; Emerald Group Publishing: Bingley, UK, 1968. [Google Scholar]
  25. Case, J.H. A Class of Games Having Pareto Optimal Nash Equilibrium. Optimiz. Theory Appl. 1974, 13, 378–385. [Google Scholar]
  26. Mamedov, M.B. On a Pareto-Optimal Nash Equilibrium. Izv. Akad. Nauk Azerb. Ser. Fiz. Tekh. 1983, 4, 11–17. [Google Scholar]
  27. Podinovskii, V.V.; Noghin, V.D. Pareto-Optimal Solutions of Multicriteria Problems; Fizmatlit: Moscow, Russia, 2007. [Google Scholar]
  28. Lazarev, V.V.; Lipen, S.V. Theory of State and Law; Urait: Moscow, Russia, 2000. [Google Scholar]
  29. Leist, O.E. Sanctions in the Soviet Law; Gos. Izd. Yurid. Lit: Moscow, Russia, 1962. [Google Scholar]
  30. Biltchev, S.V. εZ Equilibrium in a Differential Game Described by a Parabolic System. In Many Players Differential Game; Technical University: Rousse, Bulgaria, 1984; pp. 47–52. [Google Scholar]
  31. Dochev, D.T.; Stojanov, N.V. Existence of Z-Equilibrium in a Differential Game with Delay. In Many Players Differential Game; Technical University: Rousse, Bulgaria, 1984; pp. 64–72. [Google Scholar]
  32. Gaidov, S.D. Z-Equilibrium in Stochastic Differential Game. In Many Players Differential Game; Technical University: Rousse, Bulgaria, 1984. [Google Scholar]
  33. Rashkov, P.I. Sufficient Conditions for Z-Equilibrium in a Differential Game in Banach Space. In Many Players Differential Game; Technical University: Rousse, Bulgaria, 1984; pp. 91–99. [Google Scholar]
  34. Tersian, S.A. On the Z-Equilibrium Points in a Differential Game. In Many Players Differential Game; Technical University: Rousse, Bulgaria, 1984; pp. 106–111. [Google Scholar]
  35. Chernikov, S.N. Linear Inequalities; Nauka: Moscow, Russia, 1968. [Google Scholar]
  36. Zhukovskaya, L.V. Risk in a Noncooperative Game under Uncertainty. Proc. Inst. Math. Inf. Udmurt State Univ. 2014, 2, 79–84. [Google Scholar]
  37. Zhukovskiy, V.I. Some Problems of Non-Antagonistic Differential Games. In Mathematical Methods in Operations Research; Bulgarian Academy of Sciences: Sofia, Bulgaria, 1985. [Google Scholar]
  38. Pareto, V. Manuel D’Economie [Economics Textbook]; Geard: Paris, France, 1909. [Google Scholar]
  39. Blackwell, D.; Girshick, M.A. Theory of Games and Statistical; Decisions; John Wiley & Sons: New York, NY, USA, 1954. [Google Scholar]
  40. Krasovskii, N.N.; Subbotin, A.I. Positional Differential Games; Nauka: Moscow, Russia, 1985. [Google Scholar]
  41. Zhukovskiy, V.I.; Salukvadze, M.E. The Vector-Valued Maximin; Academic Press: New York, NY, USA, 1994. [Google Scholar]
  42. Nureev, R.; Petrakov, P. Economic Sanctions against Russia: Expectations and Reality; Knorus: Moscow, Russia, 2017. [Google Scholar]
  43. Nureev, R.M.; Busygin, E.G. Economic Sanctions against Russia and Russian Anti-sanctions: Costs and Benefits of Confrontation; Knorus: Moscow, Russia, 2018. [Google Scholar]
  44. Zhukovskiy, V.I.; Salukvadze, M.E. Some Game-Theoretic Problems of Control and Their Applications; Metsniereba: Tbilisi, Georgia, 1998. [Google Scholar]
  45. Gantmacher, F.R. The Theory of Matrices; Chelsea Publishing: New York, NY, USA, 1959; Volume 1–2. [Google Scholar]
  46. Voevodin, V.V.; Kuznetsov, Y.A. Matrices and Calculations; Nauka: Moscow, Russia, 1984. [Google Scholar]
  47. Calvo, E.; Rubio, S.J. Dynamic models of international environmental agreements: A differential game approach. Int. Rev. Environ. Resour. Econ. 2012, 6, 289–339. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  48. Kaempfer, W.H.; Lowenberg, A.D. The political economy of economic sanctions. Handb. Def. Econ. 2007, 2, 867–911. [Google Scholar]
  49. Lacy, D.; Niou, E.M. A theory of economic sanctions and issue linkage: The roles of preferences, information, and threats. J. Politics 2004, 66, 25–42. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  50. Whang, T. Structural estimation of economic sanctions: From initiation to outcomes. J. Peace Res. 2010, 47, 561–573. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  51. Onder, M. Regime type, issue type and economic sanctions: The role of domestic players. Economies 2019, 8, 2. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  52. Kustra, T. Economic sanctions as deterrents and constraints. J. Peace Res. 2023, 60, 649–660. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  53. Dong, Y.; Li, C. Economic sanction games among the US, the EU and Russia: Payoffs and potential effects. Econ. Model. 2018, 73, 117–128. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  54. Reddy, P.V.; Engwerda, J.C. Pareto optimality in infinite horizon linear quadratic differential games. Automatica 2013, 49, 1705–1714. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  55. Inga, J.; Bischoff, E.; Molloy, T.L.; Flad, M.; Hohmann, S. Solution sets for inverse non-cooperative linear-quadratic differential games. IEEE Control Syst. Lett. 2019, 3, 871–876. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  56. Huang, Y.; Zhang, T.; Zhu, Q. The inverse problem of linear-quadratic differential games: When is a control strategies profile Nash? In Proceedings of the 2022 58th Annual Allerton Conference on Communication, Control, and Computing (Allerton), Monticello, IL, USA, 27–30 September 2022; IEEE: Piscataway, NJ, USA, 2022; pp. 1–7. [Google Scholar]
  57. Cappello, D.; Mylvaganam, T. Approximate Nash equilibrium solutions of linear quadratic differential games. IFAC-PapersOnLine 2020, 53, 6685–6690. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
  58. Zhukovskiy, V.I.; Gorbatov, A.S.; Kudryavtsev, K.N. Berge and Nash equilibria in a linear-quadratic differential game. Autom. Remote Control 2020, 81, 2108–2131. [Google Scholar] [CrossRef]
Disclaimer/Publisher’s Note: The statements, opinions and data contained in all publications are solely those of the individual author(s) and contributor(s) and not of MDPI and/or the editor(s). MDPI and/or the editor(s) disclaim responsibility for any injury to people or property resulting from any ideas, methods, instructions or products referred to in the content.

Share and Cite

MDPI and ACS Style

Zhukovskiy, V.I.; Zhukovskaya, L.V. On the Concept of Equilibrium in Sanctions and Countersanctions in a Differential Game. Mathematics 2023, 11, 4402. https://doi.org/10.3390/math11204402

AMA Style

Zhukovskiy VI, Zhukovskaya LV. On the Concept of Equilibrium in Sanctions and Countersanctions in a Differential Game. Mathematics. 2023; 11(20):4402. https://doi.org/10.3390/math11204402

Chicago/Turabian Style

Zhukovskiy, Vladislav I., and Lidiya V. Zhukovskaya. 2023. "On the Concept of Equilibrium in Sanctions and Countersanctions in a Differential Game" Mathematics 11, no. 20: 4402. https://doi.org/10.3390/math11204402

Note that from the first issue of 2016, this journal uses article numbers instead of page numbers. See further details here.

Article Metrics

Back to TopTop